Family Law Article Harv. L. Rev. 1501

Pragmatic Family Law

Response:

Download

Introduction

Family law stands at the center of America’s culture wars. Whether regulating access to abortion, debating parental rights in education, or controlling gender-affirming care for children, states are choosing starkly different, often deeply contentious, paths that track familiar political divisions.1 Polarization in family law is neither new nor surprising for an area that implicates bodily autonomy, parenting, religion, and equality in numerous dimensions, including race, class, sexual orientation, and gender identity.2 Some disagreement is inevitable, indeed healthy, but the hyper-politicization of family law poses serious risks to children and families, making them pawns in fights for political power, distracting attention from their concrete needs, and impeding the constructive evolution of law and policy.3

Focusing on the headlines, however, obscures an equally important phenomenon. Across the broad domain of contemporary family law,4 many doctrines and policies are not polarized, even when they raise the most socially and politically sensitive issues.5 Instead, much of family law evinces convergence.6 Despite strong and conflicting views on corporal punishment, for example, every state recognizes a parental privilege to use reasonable corporal punishment, with courts justifying the privilege with consistent reasoning: as a critical restraint on the power of the state.7 Similarly, states across the country, including those not known for public investments in families, are embracing universal prekindergarten, with Oklahoma an early leader and states like Alabama and Mississippi investing in quality programs.8

Many instances of convergence in family law emerge after intense contestation — that is, issues become depolarized over time. In this category, states end up with similar rules and policies on once-divisive issues, and public support tends to coalesce around the new doctrine or policy. Most states, for example, have legalized gestational surrogacy and permit adoptees to access adoption records, issues that were once deeply contested.9 Marriage equality — the right of two adults to marry, regardless of sex — is a paradigmatic example of consensus following division. For two decades, the issue drove political cleavages.10 But by the time the Supreme Court decided Obergefell v. Hodges,11 public support for marriage equality was strong.12 This support continues to grow, although the Court’s reversal on abortion in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization13 cast doubt on the lifespan of Obergefell as a matter of constitutional doctrine, and there is ongoing resistance to marriage equality from some quarters.14

Even when state laws and policies are not uniform, pluralism on contentious issues does not necessarily reflect a red-blue divide. Conservative states, for example, might be expected to hew closely to traditional notions of parentage, granting legal rights only to adults with marital or biogenetic ties to a child. But a map of states that embrace the functional parenthood doctrine, which grants legal rights to a person who serves the psychological and functional role of a parent, looks nothing like familiar red and blue patterns.15 And a list of states that have adopted some version of a pregnant workers fairness act, which requires employers to make reasonable accommodations for pregnant workers, similarly defies reductionist partisan labels.16

What — if anything — ties together these widespread but underappreciated patterns of convergence, depolarization, and nonpartisan pluralism in family law? Intuitively, they seem to share a pragmatic approach to decision- and policymaking, that is, focusing on what works to help children and families. But pragmatism is more than a colloquial shorthand for practical solutions. It is also a method with a distinct lineage in American thought and broad application in contemporary scholarship and advocacy. American pragmatism traces to late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century philosophers, most notably Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey, who were dissatisfied with then-dominant modes of thinking that laid claim to certainty about the source of ideas.17 The early pragmatists proposed an alternative method that focused not on first principles but instead on whether an idea was useful in clarifying or resolving a philosophical dispute.18 They argued that all ideas are tentative and subject to testing and revision based on empirical evidence and experimentation.19 And they were pluralist in their understanding of knowledge, looking to lived experience as well as more traditional sources of empirical evidence.20 Advocates and scholars have adapted pragmatism to address social problems, from Dewey’s project of reforming American public education to more recent efforts to encourage modern social movements.21 In short, the living tradition of American pragmatism offers an approach to understanding and solving problems.22

As this Article argues, convergence, depolarization, and nonpartisan pluralism in contemporary family law evince deep, underlying commonalities that reflect the pragmatic method.23 Across disparate areas, judges, legislators, administrators, and others are largely setting aside abstract ideals and political ideology and instead focusing on whether a doctrine or policy promotes core aspects of family and child well-being, such as a child’s need for a consistent caregiver and a family’s need for basic resources. And decisionmakers are drawing on experience-based learning, empirical evidence, and experimentation. Finally, decisionmakers are finding context-specific solutions, because what works in one setting may not work in another. This Article terms this approach to decision- and policymaking pragmatic family law.24

The doctrine of functional parenthood provides an apt illustration. Traditional parentage laws embody abstract ideals and dominant norms, grounding legal parentage in marriage and biogenetics.25 But lives are complex, and adults without marital or biogenetic ties often raise children. Courts developed the functional parenthood doctrine to address this reality.26 In case after case, family courts eschew broad pronouncements about acceptable and unacceptable family forms.27 Instead, courts listen to families and ask a specific question: whether formalizing an arrangement with an adult who is already caring for the child will promote the well-being of this child.28 In making this contextualized decision, courts rely on empirical evidence about the importance of stability between a child and caregiver, and courts center the experiences of affected families.29 As a result, family courts often ratify nontraditional family forms.30

The example of functional parenthood also illustrates the category of nonpartisan pluralism. As noted above, the states that have embraced the doctrine do not fall neatly into a political category. Instead, the doctrine has taken root where courts find themselves especially in need of a tool to promote stability in a child’s life. As a result of opioid overdose deaths and opioid use disorder, for example, many parents either have died or are incapacitated.31 Only four percent of children nationwide live with neither parent,32 but in some parts of Appalachia, more than a third of all students live with a relative or other caregiver, sometimes a teacher or neighbor.33 It is unsurprising, then, that Kentucky, which has a high concentration of opioid overdose deaths,34 is by far the country’s leader in functional parenthood cases.35

This Article does not argue that the pragmatic method is the singular driving force behind convergence, depolarization, and nonpartisan pluralism in contemporary family law. There are many dynamics at play, and, true to pragmatism, the Article does not espouse a grand theory to explain all of family law or propose one path forward. This Article does argue that the patterns, at core, reflect a common method and, more importantly, that highlighting this methodological through line generates useful insights for scholars, legal actors, and advocates seeking to improve child and family well-being in an era of polarization.

Explicitly recognizing the pragmatic method in family law — that is, naming the tools that legal actors are already using — provides guidance about what is possible in the current political climate.36 Family law is fertile ground for the pragmatic method because promoting child well-being is foundational to family law,37 and pragmatism provides a tool to further this goal. As the Article demonstrates, pragmatic family law has led to substantial improvements in the well-being of children and families, contributing, for example, to the historic drop in child poverty for all racial groups over the last few decades.38 Further, naming this approach invites a debate about its relative merits compared to more familiar approaches to decisionmaking, such as rights-based litigation and discourse, and values-based debates.39 All three approaches have a role to play. Rights play an important role in family law, and it is critical to talk about values in many contexts. But naming pragmatism as a distinct tool encourages discussion about how these approaches can work separately and together.

Crystallizing methodological commonalities around pragmatism also has doctrinal and institutional implications. A perennial concern in family law doctrine is the ubiquity of open-ended standards, including the equitable distribution and best interests of the child standards. Scholars have long criticized the indeterminacy of these standards, arguing that they empower judges to make value-laden decisions with virtually unfettered discretion.40 Pragmatism is one way of grounding these inqui­ries, providing methodological guidance for courts: rely on the lived experience of family members, use empirical evidence, and make contextualized decisions. This echoes what advocates and scholars have long argued courts should do in family law cases, but pragmatism provides a template and set of expectations for judicial decisions.41 Likewise, elevating the pragmatic method in family law highlights institutions that already — intentionally or not — deploy the approach. Identifying these institutions provides guidance for reforming the many institutions of family law that might also use the method productively but are not currently doing so.42

Finally, naming pragmatism as a distinct approach underscores its significant limitations, at least as constrained by the modern political context. Thus far, the method has not dislodged family law’s system of privatized dependency; family members still bear primary responsibility for caregiving, with limited support from the state.43 And pragmatism has a mixed record on addressing racial inequity. Many of the examples of pragmatic family law identified in this Article, such as the Earned Income Tax Credit, Medicaid expansion, and universal prekindergarten, have helped reduce racial gaps between families.44 But this progress comes with a critical caveat: there is relatively broad public support for pragmatic doctrines and policies when they are not framed as redressing racial inequity and instead are cast in race-neutral terms.45 Indeed, one of the starkest divides in the United States is disagreement about the government’s role in addressing racial inequity.46 Thus, when a problem is understood to affect primarily families of color, race has trumped pragmatism.47 The functional parenthood example illustrates this phenomenon. It is part of a larger story about family law’s (mostly) compassionate response to the opioid epidemic. Legal actors are using the pragmatic method to support families affected by the epidemic, including keeping families together and providing treatment for parents.48 During the crack epidemic, by contrast, legal actors pathologized Black parents and made little effort to blunt the impact of the epidemic on families.49

This Article surfaces this trade-off: pragmatic family law is advancing the well-being of children and families of color, but it is doing so obliquely. As a matter of values, this means the United States is not reckoning with our history of racism and ongoing racial inequities. And, as an instrumental matter, it means family law is not developing policies that tackle the root causes of racial inequity. Accordingly, this Article does not argue pragmatic family law is a panacea but rather describes what pragmatic family law has — and has not — accomplished, prompting debate about the relative merits of different approaches to addressing racial inequity.

In short, this Article makes three contributions to the literature. It identifies and tracks in detail patterns in contemporary family law that defy the polarized contestation all too present in high-profile doctrines and policies. The Article then looks to American pragmatism to find a methodological link in these underappreciated patterns. Finally, by connecting the patterns with a conversation that has been unfolding for 150 years about knowledge and problem-solving, the Article draws lessons about the utility and limits of the pragmatic method in family law. Most notably, identifying the pragmatic method as a distinct approach to family law decision- and policymaking encourages scholars to debate its relative merits as compared with rights-based and values-based approaches, and it encourages legal actors and practitioners to deploy pragmatism more consciously, where and when appropriate.

The Article proceeds as follows: Part I describes polarization in family law, names some of the forces driving the phenomenon, and identifies the harms it poses to the well-being of children and families. The Article then provides granular observations about convergence, depolarization, and nonpartisan pluralism in family law. Following the pragmatic method, Part II seeks to learn from these examples to suggest a hypothesis for linking disparate strands in contemporary doctrine and policy, and it finds that commonality in the pragmatic method. Part III explores the heft of that methodological linkage, sketching lessons for scholars, legal actors, and advocates. It examines the scope, scale, and place of pragmatic family law as compared with other approaches to decisionmaking. It identifies the significant achievements of pragmatic family law in furthering child and family well-being as well as the larger social challenges that limit the utility of the approach. The Article concludes that recognizing pragmatic family law as an explicit method and understanding its place among other approaches helps scholars, advocates, and legal actors better and more purposefully deploy this tool in the law reform toolbox, guiding both doctrinal and institutional reforms.

Continue Reading in the Full PDF


* Joseph M. McLaughlin Professor of Law, Fordham Law School. For helpful suggestions and insights, I am grateful to Sania Anwar, Susan Appleton, Wendy Bach, Jessica Bulman-Pozen, Emily Buss, Naomi Cahn, June Carbone, Kristin Collins, Courtney Cox, Catherine Davidson, Nestor Davidson, Nancy Dowd, Maxine Eichner, Kris Franklin, Jennifer Gordon, Lisa Grumet, Josh Gupta-Kagan, Henry Huntington, Courtney Joslin, Ethan Leib, James Liebman, Solangel Maldonado, Linda McClain, Douglas NeJaime, Kimani Paul-Emile, David Pozen, Clare Ryan, Aaron Saiger, Carol Sanger, Elizabeth Scott, Robert Scott, Jane Spinak, Lisa Washington, Deborah Widiss, Yiran Zhang, and Benjamin Zipursky, as well as workshop participants at the Berkeley Poverty Law Conference, Columbia Law School, the Family Law Scholars and Teachers Conference, the New York Area Family Law Scholars Workshop, and the North Carolina Law Review 2022 Symposium on Families, Crisis, and Economic Security: Rethink-ing the Role of Government. For excellent research assistance, I thank Teresa Huang, Karl Kristensen, Isaac Lunt, and Anna Belle Newport, and for outstanding editing, I am grateful to the Harvard Law Review.

Footnotes
  1. ^ See infra section I.A.1, pp. 1512–16. This Article focuses on the ideological polarization of substantive family law doctrine and policy: legal actors choosing widely divergent laws and policies, such as some states banning all or most abortions and other states enacting measures to protect access to abortion. See Jacob Grumbach, Laboratories Against Democracy 181 (2022) (“[P]olarization is fundamentally about the distance between the parties.”). As discussed below, numerous forces drive this polarization. See infra section I.A.2, pp. 1516–21.

    Return to citation ^
  2. ^ Family law’s expressive function amplifies the stakes of regulation. See Clare Huntington, Staging the Family, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 589, 608–39 (2013) (describing family life as performative and explaining how family performances shape legal conceptions of the family); Carl E. Schneider, The Channelling Function in Family Law, 20 Hofstra L. Rev. 495, 498 (1992) (“[T]he expressive function [of family law] . . . deploy[s] the law’s power to impart ideas through words and symbols. It has two (related) aspects: Law’s expressive abilities may be used, first, to provide a voice in which citizens may speak and, second, to alter the behavior of people the law addresses.”).

    Return to citation ^
  3. ^ See infra section I.A.3, pp. 1521–23.

    Return to citation ^
  4. ^ This Article defines family law to include both the direct and indirect regulation of families. Direct regulation creates legal categories of family and governs entry and exit from these categories, determines the rights and responsibilities that flow from family status, and regulates behavior within families, such as family violence; indirect regulation structures the larger context of family life and includes a broad range of doctrine and policy. See Clare Huntington, Failure to Flourish: How Law Undermines Family Relationships 59–68 (2014). This broad def­inition is consistent with other family law scholarship. See Maxine Eichner, The Family, In Context, 128 Harv. L. Rev. 1980, 1981–82 (2015) (book review) (“Fueled by the recognition that families are social institutions profoundly affected by their social and economic contexts, and that an increasing range of families are being destabilized by these contexts, the emerging scholarship of the 2010s situates families, including nontraditional families, within their surrounding world.” (footnote omitted)); Kerry Abrams, Family History: Inside and Out, 111 Mich. L. Rev. 1001, 1003–05 (2013) (book review) (distinguishing family law, traditionally defined as marriage, divorce, and related issues such as parentage, from “the law of the family,” which includes “the many ways in which families are created, shaped, and constrained by law,” id. at 1003, including tax law, contract law, property law, welfare law, criminal law, tort law, and so on).

    Return to citation ^
  5. ^ Polarization in family law is well documented, see generally Naomi Cahn & June Carbone, Red Families v. Blue Families: Legal Polarization and the Creation of Culture (2011), but most family law scholars have not addressed ways family law is not polarized. A few family law scholars have noted specific instances of nonpartisan pluralism, see infra notes 211–14, 341–46 and accompanying text (discussing the work of Professor Deborah Widiss); infra notes 335–40 and accompanying text (discussing the work of Professors Courtney Joslin and Douglas NeJaime); see also June Carbone & Naomi Cahn, Judging Families, 77 UMKC L. Rev. 267, 287–90 (2008) (exploring the possibility that family courts can productively resolve issues such as same-sex parenting and custody battles), but scholars have yet to put these isolated examples in a larger context or offer a conceptual framework to link them. This Article thus returns to a theme I briefly introduced when reviewing Red Families v. Blue Families: after arguing that the authors’ proposed solutions to polarization of changing the subject and devolving authority to the states would be largely ineffective, I suggested that family law should “develop a pragmatic program for bridging the divide that neither avoids true differences nor retreats to balkanized localism.” Clare Huntington, Purple Haze, 109 Mich. L. Rev. 903, 904 (2011) (book review).

    Return to citation ^
  6. ^ See infra section I.B.1, pp. 1524–27.

    Return to citation ^
  7. ^ See infra notes 130–33 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  8. ^ See infra notes 140–43 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  9. ^ See infra notes 156–68 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  10. ^ See infra notes 169–71 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  11. ^ 135 S. Ct. 2584 (2015).

    Return to citation ^
  12. ^ See infra note 173 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  13. ^ 142 S. Ct. 2228, 2242 (2022).

    Return to citation ^
  14. ^ See infra notes 177–82 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  15. ^ See Courtney Joslin & Douglas NeJaime, How Parenthood Functions, 123 Colum. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2023) (manuscript at 32 & fig.1), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4208364 [https://perma.cc/5A35-WU43] (drawing this map, which includes recognition in states like Arkansas, Georgia, North Carolina, and South Carolina, and a lack of recognition in states like Illinois and Oregon); see also infra notes 199–202, 331–40 and accompanying text (discussing this example). This Article uses the typology of red and blue states to describe familiar political divisions in the United States. The red and blue classification typically reflects voting patterns in presidential elections, see 2020 Presidential Election Results: Biden Wins, N.Y. Times, https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2020/11/03/us/elections/results-president.html [https://perma.cc/4DR6-P4B8]; 2016 Presidential Election Results, N.Y. Times (Aug. 9, 2017, 9:00 AM), https://www.nytimes.com/elections/2016/results/president [https://perma.cc/L3YR-4KXQ], and the percentage of residents in each state who identify as, or lean, Republican or Democrat, see Party Affiliation by State, Pew Rsch. Ctr., https://www.pewresearch.org/religion/religious-landscape-study/compare/party-affiliation/by/state [https://perma.cc/ZLY4-BZ5D] (reporting the results of a 2014 study). This typology, however, fails to capture many nuances in the political landscape, both within a state and between states. See Jessica Bulman-Pozen, Partisan Federalism, 127 Harv. L. Rev. 1077, 1130–31 (2014). And, as this Article demonstrates, a state’s classification as red or blue does not always predict the kinds of policies it will adopt. See infra section I.B, pp. 1523–35. Nonetheless, the typology is a useful shorthand for capturing the political divides that contrast with pragmatic family law.

    Return to citation ^
  16. ^ See State Pregnant Workers Fairness Laws, Better Balance (Jan. 30, 2023), https://www.abetterbalance.org/resources/pregnant-worker-fairness-legislative-successes https://perma.cc/7GAV-UKJL]; see also infra notes 211–14, 341–46 and accompanying text (discussing this example).

    Return to citation ^
  17. ^ See infra section II.A, pp. 1537–43; Thomas C. Grey, Holmes and Legal Pragmatism, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 787, 788–89 (1989) (explaining the term “American pragmatism” and its intellectual roots).

    Return to citation ^
  18. ^ See infra notes 224–28 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  19. ^ See infra notes 227–28, 231 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  20. ^ See infra notes 229–34 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  21. ^ See infra notes 245–61 and accompanying text. Family law scholars largely have not examined family law through the lens of pragmatism, although some legal scholars have written about pragmatism in the context of abortion rights. See Mark S. Kende, Constitutional Pragmatism, The Supreme Court, and Democratic Revolution, 89 Denv. U. L. Rev. 635, 642, 659–60 (2012) (discussing how the Supreme Court has used pragmatic solutions, such as consideration of empirical elements and “common sense,” id. at 642, to decide abortion cases); Daniel A. Farber, Legal Pragmatism and the Constitution, 72 Minn. L. Rev. 1331, 1373–74 (1988) (distinguishing Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973), from Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), by pointing to the pragmatic reasoning of Roe — a strong consensus favoring procreative rights and an “overwhelming social consensus against the logic of the state’s position”). For the rare exception of a family law scholar using pragmatism, see David D. Meyer, Constitutional Pragmatism for a Changing American Family, 32 Rutgers L.J. 711, 712 (2001) (arguing that the Supreme Court’s decision on grandparental visitation in Troxel v. Granville, 530 U.S. 57 (2000), reflected the principles of legal pragmatism).

    Return to citation ^
  22. ^ In keeping with scholarship outside of philosophy, this Article does not use pragmatism in its strict philosophical sense but instead draws on a broader living tradition. Cf. Thomas C. Grey, Judicial Review and Legal Pragmatism, 38 Wake Forest L. Rev. 473, 478 (2003) (contrasting “jurisprudential high theory whose influence reaches only to those who take a specialized academic interest in jurisprudence” with “working legal thought, . . . the cluster of attitudes and approaches to law that lawyers take on during their apprenticeship, and then actually manifest in their work as practitioners, judges, teachers, and doctrinal commentators”); Thomas Merton, No Man Is an Island 153–54 (1955) (“Tradition is living and active, but convention is passive and dead. . . . Tradition, which is always old, is at the same time ever new because it is always reviving — born again in each new generation, to be lived and applied in a new and particular way. Convention is simply the ossification of social customs.” Id. at 153–54.). Calling pragmatism a living tradition is apt both because of the nature of the method itself, which is committed to the constant revision of ideas, see John Dewey, The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy and Other Essays in Contemporary Thought, at iv (1910), reprinted in 17 John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925–1953, at 39, 39–40 (Jo Ann Boydston ed., 1981) (stating that it is “better to view pragmatism quite vaguely as part and parcel of a general movement of intellectual reconstruction,” because “regard[ing] it as a fixed rival system making like claim to completeness and finality,” id. at 40, undercuts the goal of pragmatism: to challenge systems of belief that claim universality and finality), and because the method has had so many adaptations, see infra notes 241–61 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  23. ^ See John Dewey, Problems of Men 11–12 (1946) (contending that theories should not be universal and instead should be built on observations of the world). Relatedly, Professor Martha Albertson Fineman argues that family law should use more “[m]iddle-range theory.” Martha Albertson Fineman, The Illusion of Equality 8 (1991). This approach was developed by sociologist Robert Merton and entails starting with observations, developing a theory, then returning to observation to adjust the developing theory. See Robert K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure 39–72 (enlarged ed. 1968). Fineman describes Merton’s approach as an alternative to “grand” theorizing, Fineman, supra, at 7.

    Return to citation ^
  24. ^ This Article does not claim that legal actors explicitly invoke the pragmatic method. Instead, the argument is that the method is implicit across much doctrine and policy.

    Return to citation ^
  25. ^ See Douglas NeJaime, The Nature of Parenthood, 126 Yale L.J. 2260, 2266–67 (2017) (describing these bases for legal parenthood but also noting that unmarried fathers do not receive the same level of recognition as unmarried mothers and thus a biogenetic tie is not dispositive, at least for men).

    Return to citation ^
  26. ^ See infra notes 199–202 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  27. ^ See infra notes 331–40 and accompanying text (describing this phenomenon and an empirical study by Courtney Joslin and Douglas NeJaime making these findings).

    Return to citation ^
  28. ^ See infra notes 337–38 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  29. ^ See infra notes 339–40 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  30. ^ See infra notes 331–38 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  31. ^ See Death Rate Maps & Graphs, Ctrs. for Disease Control & Prevention (June 2, 2022), https://www.cdc.gov/drugoverdose/deaths/index.html [https://perma.cc/6VJX-TTZX] (reporting 68,630 opioid overdose deaths in 2020); Substance Abuse & Mental Health Servs. Admin., U.S. Dep’t of Health & Hum. Servs., Key Substance Use and Mental Health Indicators in the United States: Results from the 2019 National Survey on Drug Use and Health 24 (2020), https://store.samhsa.gov/sites/default/files/SAMHSA_Digital_Download/PEP20-07-01-001-PDF.pdf [https://perma.cc/57FG-VHJG] (finding approximately 10 million people misused opioids in 2019); id. at 40 (noting that people aged 18–25 have higher rates of opioid use disorder than other age groups). Opioid use disorder and especially overdoses are most common among people in peak childbearing and parenting years. Lawrence Scholl et al., Drug and Opioid-Involved Overdose Deaths — United States, 2013–2017, 67 Morbidity & Mortality Wkly. Rep. 1419, 1420 tbl.1 (2019) (showing that the highest opioid overdose death rate was for men ages 25–44).

    Return to citation ^
  32. ^ See Paul Hemez & Chanell Washington, Number of Children Living Only with Their Mothers Has Doubled in Past 50 Years, U.S. Census Bureau (Apr. 12, 2021), https://www.census.gov/library/stories/2021/04/number-of-children-living-only-with-their-mothers-has-doubled-in-past-50-years.html [https://perma.cc/6YVF-G6ZA].

    Return to citation ^
  33. ^ See Kristina Brant, Nonparental Primary Caregivers: A Case Study from the United States, in Social Parenthood in Comparative Perspective (Clare Huntington, Courtney G. Joslin & Christiane von Bary eds., forthcoming 2023) (manuscript at 95) (on file with the Harvard Law School Library) (describing this pattern in parts of Appalachia); Kristina Brant, When Mamaw Becomes Mom: Social Capital and Kinship Family Formation amid the Rural Opioid Crisis, Russell Sage Found. J. Soc. Scis., May 2022, at 78, 79 (reporting findings from Appalachian Kentucky, where “local school staff in the region estimate that as many as 40 percent of students are being raised by a relative caregiver”).

    Return to citation ^
  34. ^ See Drug Overdose Mortality by State, Ctrs. for Disease Control & Prevention, https://www.cdc.gov/nchs/pressroom/sosmap/drug_poisoning_mortality/drug_poisoning.htm [https://perma.cc/XML4-5J22].

    Return to citation ^
  35. ^ Joslin & NeJaime, supra note 15 (manuscript at 39–40, 40 tbl.1) (noting that, as measured by electronically available judicial decisions, Kentucky has the greatest number of functional parenthood cases in the country, followed by Pennsylvania and California). After adjusting for state population, the rate of functional parenthood cases in Kentucky — as reported in court decisions — is 0.27 cases per 10,000 people, as compared with 0.08 in Pennsylvania and 0.02 in California. See id. (reporting 122, 108, and 82 cases in Kentucky, Pennsylvania, and California, respectively); 2020 Population and Housing State Data, U.S. Census Bureau (Aug. 12, 2021), https://www.census.gov/library/visualizations/interactive/2020-population-and-housing-state-data.html [https://perma.cc/JB88-HJ23] (reporting populations of 4,505,836, 13,002,700, and 39,538,223 for Kentucky, Pennsylvania, and California, respectively).

    Return to citation ^
  36. ^ See infra sections III.A–B, pp. 1559–71.

    Return to citation ^
  37. ^ See Clare Huntington & Elizabeth S. Scott, Conceptualizing Legal Childhood in the Twenty-First Century, 118 Mich. L. Rev. 1371, 1397–413 (2020) (demonstrating that the modern regulation of children is intended to promote child well-being). In that article, Professor Elizabeth Scott and I drew on our experience as reporters for the American Law Institute’s Restatement of Children and the Law, id. at 1379, and identified an explanatory framework for modern regulation that centers child well-being, see id. at 1397–413. This Article addresses a new question: how to advance the interests of children and families in an era of intense political contestation, and the Article finds guidance in the living tradition of American pragmatism.

    Return to citation ^
  38. ^ See infra notes 390–98 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  39. ^ See infra sections III.A–B, pp. 1559–71. Rights-based litigation as an approach to decisionmaking is self-explanatory, but the terms “values-based approach” and “values-based debate” need some elaboration. This Article uses these terms to refer to a mode of decisionmaking that emphasizes broad values, such as autonomy, fairness, dignity, and equality, and centers debate around these abstract principles. As the Article makes clear, family law can and should take these and other values into account, see infra section III.A, pp. 1559–65, and pragmatic family law itself embraces the value of child and family well-being. For further discussion of the relationship between the three approaches to family law, see infra sections III.A–B, pp. 1559–71.

    Return to citation ^
  40. ^ See infra notes 266, 423–25 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  41. ^ See infra notes 423–28 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  42. ^ Institutional analysis is relatively new to family law. See Clare Huntington, The Institutions of Family Law, 102 B.U. L. Rev. 393, 413–19 (2022). This Article shows the benefits of deploying this form of analysis.

    Return to citation ^
  43. ^ See infra notes 366–68 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  44. ^ See infra notes 390–97 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  45. ^ See infra notes 399–400 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  46. ^ See Pew Rsch. Ctr., Beyond Red vs. Blue: The Political Typology 7 (2021), https://www.pewresearch.org/politics/wp-content/uploads/sites/4/2021/11/PP_2021.11.09_political-typology_REPORT.pdf [https://perma.cc/D8K8-2GVE] (“Perhaps no issue is more divisive than racial injustice in the U.S. Among the four Republican-oriented typology groups, no more than about a quarter say a lot more needs to be done to ensure equal rights for all Americans regardless of their racial or ethnic background; by comparison, no fewer than about three-quarters of any Democratic group say a lot more needs to be done to achieve this goal.”).

    Return to citation ^
  47. ^ See id.; infra notes 400, 407–09 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  48. ^ See infra notes 402–06 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  49. ^ See infra notes 407–09 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^