Constitutional Interpretation
Democratic Justice: Felix Frankfurter, The Supreme Court, and the Making of the Liberal Establishment
By Brad Snyder. New York, N.Y.: W.W. Norton & Company. 2022. Pp. 979. $45.00.
On the fourth floor of the Harvard Law School Library sits Justice Felix Frankfurterâs rocking chair. It was a fitting seat for Frankfurter, an intellectual in constant motion. Georgetown Law Professor Brad Snyderâs new biography of Frankfurter, Democratic Justice,1×1. Brad Snyder, Democratic Justice: Felix Frankfurter, The Supreme Court, and the Making of the Liberal Establishment (2022). tells the story of a restless truth-seeker. Snyder expertly illustrates how Frankfurter never wavered in his deep commitment to democracy and how Frankfurterâs belief in objective truth informed his democratic convictions. But Snyder does not grapple with a potential inconsistency on Frankfurterâs part. Amidst his lifelong pursuit of truth, Frankfurter was at times unusually reticent to seek, find, and enforce definitive answers in the realm of constitutional interpretation. When confronted with certain constitutional questions, especially ones that pitted the majorityâs power to govern against the rights of individuals, Frankfurter sometimes did something out of character. He stopped.
Frankfurter immigrated to America from Vienna as a boy without knowing any English,2×2. Id. at 9. graduated first in his Harvard Law School class,3×3. Id. at 24. fought for the constitutionality of minimum wage and maximum hours labor laws,4×4. Id. at 81â82. appointed students to Supreme Court clerkships and other governmental posts while a Harvard Law professor,5×5. Id. at 7, 76. played an influential role in the infamous Sacco and Vanzetti case,6×6. See id. at 160â83. worked as a behind-the-scenes leader of the Zionist movement,7×7. See id. at 105â16, 490â91. helped craft landmark New Deal legislation,8×8. See id. at 219â22. advised President Franklin Delano Roosevelt,9×9. Id. at 246â53, 312. was the subject of an FBI file,10×10. Id. at 545. and served as a Supreme Court Justice.
Many have claimed that the ideological direction of Frankfurterâs relentless flurry of activity was inconsistent: they frame him as a political progressiveâturnedâjudicial conservative.11×11. Id. at 4, 349, 393, 481, 601. Snyder upends this conventional wisdom.12×12. See id. at 393, 536. He deftly traces how Frankfurterâs vigorous progressive political commitments informed his conservative (or rather, restrained) judicial philosophy.13×13. See id. at 427.
Frankfurterâs commitment to seeking truth sustained his enduring commitment to democracy. Unlike his avowed idol,14×14. See id. at 66â67, 69â70, 198â99, 245â46. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,15×15. See id. at 49 (âEver the skeptic, Holmes thought that there was no such thing as truth, which he defined as âthe system of my (intellectual) limitationsâ or âthe majority vote of that nation that could lick all others.ââ). Frankfurter was a âstark empiricistâ16×16. Id. at 219. and a firm believer in âobjective truth.â17×17. Id. at 49. And he insisted that the American people, not judges, were the most capable of realizing truths at scale and thus achieving socially optimal outcomes.18×18. See id. at 416 (explaining Frankfurterâs âdemocratic faithâ). It followed that unelected judges should get out of their way.
But to hold fast to this âdemocratic faith,â19×19. Id. at times Frankfurter broke with its very foundations: he often did not apply his belief in the need to seek, find, and then live by objective truths to questions of constitutional law. Frankfurter was devoted to Professor James Bradley Thayerâs theory of judicial restraint, which prevents judges from invalidating democratic legislation even if they believe it might be unconstitutional.20×20. See id. at 20â21. The judgeâs own sense of true constitutional meaning in close cases is irrelevant; he can set aside legislation only if its unconstitutionality is âclear beyond a reasonable doubt.â21×21. James Bradley Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law 25 (Boston, Little, Brown & Co. 1893). Such judicial restraint â to which Frankfurter was explicitly committed22×22. See Snyder, supra note 1, at 20â21, 710.  â is not grounded in a belief that the people are superior interpreters of constitutional meaning. Rather, the theory posits that often there is no constitutional meaning clear enough to constrain the democratic branches â especially when those branches come into conflict with individual rights.23×23. See Thayer, supra note 21, at 18.
Granted, the Framers did set forth a capacious, forgiving plan for politics in the form of the Constitution. That âframework for government,â to use Frankfurterâs phrasing, empowers us to govern ourselves largely as we see fit.24×24. Snyder, supra note 1, at 555 (quoting Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 610 (1952) (Frankfurter, J., concurring)). But its flexibility has limits.25×25. See, e.g., U.S. Const. amends. IâX, XIV. Perhaps too taken with a faith in American democracy that he himself likened to religious zeal,26×26. See Snyder, supra note 1, at 348, 353, 420. Frankfurter sometimes did not enforce those limits. Thus, Snyder paints readers a wonderful portrait of a thinker and doer who is an inspiration, but also a caution.
While tracing Frankfurterâs tremendous professional career, Snyder profiles Frankfurter the person, providing countless anecdotes that reveal his insatiable âzest for life.â27×27. Id. at 413. As one of his contemporaries explained, Frankfurter âcollect[ed] peopleâ rather than âbooks or pictures.â28×28. Id. at 38. Snyder relates how Frankfurterâs charismatic personality and first-rate mind fueled his meteoric rise. As Frankfurter once wrote: âSo much of it . . . is personalia.â29×29. Id. at 108.
Indeed it was: human connections help explain every success of Frankfurterâs staggering career. Having become one of thenâU.S. Attorney Henry Stimsonâs âsurrogate sonsâ while working for him in the Southern District of New York,30×30. Id. at 29; see also id. at 27. Frankfurter landed the job with Stimson thanks to the recommendation of Harvard Law School Dean James Barr Ames. See id. Frankfurter followed Stimson to the War Department.31×31. Id. at 37. During World War I, President Woodrow Wilson selected Frankfurter to chair the War Labor Policies Board, where he grew close with the Assistant Secretary of the Navy, Franklin Delano Roosevelt.32×32. Id. at 98â100. About a decade later, Frankfurter (by then a Harvard Law professor) publicly supported then-Governor Roosevelt during his successful 1932 presidential campaign.33×33. Id. at 211â13.
As a professor, Frankfurter wielded immense influence by placing his best students in positions of power throughout government. He was a meritocrat through and through,34×34. Id. at 66 (âWhat mattered was not [his studentsâ] social standing but their brains, their ideas, and their future goals.â); see also id. at 337 (recounting how Frankfurter translated his belief in meritocracy into civil service reform during the Roosevelt Administration). and he enjoyed cultivating the brightest minds and then handpicking them for Supreme Court clerkships.35×35. Id. at 76. Once Roosevelt became President, Frankfurter became a âone-man recruiting agencyâ who sent student after student to work for the Administration.36×36. Id. at 224.
Frankfurterâs commitment to his students was unbreakable. âNothing . . . could shake Frankfurterâs loyalty to his former students,â even to credibly accused Soviet spies like Alger Hiss.37×37. Id. at 547; see also id. at 532â36. Frankfurterâs many influential protĂ©gĂ©s reciprocated his loyalty. For example, Frankfurter acolytes helped persuade President Roosevelt to nominate Frankfurter to fill the late Justice Cardozoâs seat in 1939.38×38. See id. at 284. Even after President Rooseveltâs death, Frankfurter continued to exert influence in part thanks to friends and former students. See, e.g., id. at 443, 460â62, 467.
Frankfurterâs loyalty and ability to âcollect[] peopleâ faced a tall test on the ego- and conflict-ridden Supreme Court.39×39. See generally Noah Feldman, Scorpions: The Battles and Triumphs of FDRâs Great Supreme Court Justices (2010). For perhaps the first time in his life, Felix Frankfurter did not pass a test with flying colors. Mutual animosity â particularly his rivalries with Justices Black and Douglas40×40. See Snyder, supra note 1, at 390, 393, 410â11, 414, 595, 602.  â prevented Frankfurter from becoming more influential on the Court.41×41. See id. at 568 (âFrankfurter was not an effective coalition builder and often alienated his colleagues with long, pedantic conference remarks.â). Indeed, Professor Noah Feldman has concluded that the âhigh point of Frankfurterâs judicial influenceâ came in 1940, only about one year into his Supreme Court tenure. Feldman, supra note 39, at 185. Although his intellectual disagreements with his colleagues were real, they grew insurmountable when layered atop the Justicesâ deep personal distaste for one another.42×42. See, e.g., Snyder, supra note 1, at 390, 393. A monumental exception to this dynamic was Frankfurterâs role in Brown v. Board of Education.43×43. 347 U.S. 483 (1954). Snyder mounts a persuasive case that Frankfurter played an essential role in forming a fragile consensus to invalidate de jure segregation in public schools.44×44. See Snyder, supra note 1, at 594.
The many hours Frankfurter spent outside of his âmarble prisonâ45×45. Id. at 362. advising President Roosevelt also inhibited his judicial success: âFrankfurterâs active social life and yen for policy making forced him to sacrifice judicial craftsmanship,â46×46. Id. at 412. such that his âopinions were often only as good as his law clerkâs editing skills.â47×47. Id. at 413.
His advising activities led to ethical lapses as well. â[I]n advising Roosevelt and [Secretary of War] Stimson on issues that might come before the Court, Frankfurter . . . cross[ed] dangerous ethical lines . . . .â48×48. Id. at 365. For example, Frankfurter counseled Secretary Stimson regarding a case of suspected Nazi saboteurs, which was âbound to come before the Court.â49×49. Id. at 395. Frankfurter did not disqualify himself from the case, even as he pushed Justice Murphy to do so given his Army Reserve post.50×50. Id. at 397.
While Frankfurter bent certain rules, he did not veer from his commitment to judicial restraint. He had long lambasted judicial overreach. As an attorney and professor, he waged a decades-long fight in court51×51. See id. at 74, 81â82. and in the pages of the Harvard Law Review52×52. Id. at 129, 140 (citing Felix Frankfurter, Twenty Years of Mr. Justice Holmesâ Constitutional Opinions, 36 Harv. L. Rev. 909, 915, 919, 932 (1923)). against judges using the Due Process Clauses of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to legislate from the bench.53×53. See id. at 149, 157â58, 197. He continued this fight as a Justice even as the Warren Court used those very same provisions to achieve politically progressive ends that he supported.54×54. See id. at 649; see also id. at 523 (â[T]oo many so-called liberals . . . are seduced by what Justice Brandeis rightly called the âodious doctrine that the end justified the means.ââ (omission in original)). All the while, Frankfurter recognized that those clauses guarantee minimum procedural due process rights.55×55. See id. at 176â77, 537â38, 568.
Frankfurterâs lifelong critique of judges leveraging open-ended constitutional language to invalidate legislation is well taken, and Democratic Justice ultimately serves as a monument to his philosophy of restraint. As Dean John Manning has argued, the Constitution, like most laws, contains a number of compromises between competing values.56×56. John F. Manning, Separation of Powers as Ordinary Interpretation, 124 Harv. L. Rev. 1939, 1945 (2011) (noting âthe Philadelphia Conventionâs countless compromisesâ). Vague constitutional principles and purposes might be insufficient grounds for undoing democratically enacted legislation.57×57. Id. at 1948 (â[W]here no specific clause speaks directly to the question at issue, interpreters must respect the documentâs indeterminacy.â). On the other hand, the judiciary must enforce compromises that the Framers did reach and enshrine in our supreme law.58×58. See id. at 1947 (âWhere the Constitution is specific, the Court should read it the way it reads all specific texts.â).
When assessed under this framework, at times Frankfurterâs otherwise compelling democratic philosophy of judicial restraint slipped into an unwillingness to allow enduring constitutional commands to trump the passing will of the people.59×59. But see, e.g., Snyder, supra note 1, at 440, 595 (describing Frankfurterâs enforcement of the Equal Protection Clause to invalidate racially discriminatory laws and executive actions); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296, 311 (1940) (upholding a petitionerâs free speech claim under the âclear and present dangerâ standard, with Frankfurter in the unanimous majority). Indeed, he sided with the majority in a number of âanticanonâ cases,60×60. See generally Jamal Greene, The Anticanon, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 379 (2011). including Hirabayashi v. United States61×61. 320 U.S. 81 (1943). and Korematsu v. United States.62×62. 323 U.S. 214 (1944). Snyder casts Frankfurterâs role in these cases in too forgiving a light. For example, he writes that âFrankfurterâs concurrence in Korematsu . . . was as close as he could come to dissenting from the awful decision.â63×63. Snyder, supra note 1, at 450. But it was nonetheless a concurrence, not a dissent.64×64. Korematsu, 323 U.S. at 224 (Frankfurter, J., concurring).
Frankfurterâs commitment to judicial restraint was in some tension with his devotion to seeking truth. It is striking that the highest form of praise Frankfurter bestowed on others was declaring that they had searched for, discovered, and then lived by truth. Yet his own jurisprudence cannot be characterized in those same terms.
When commemorating the life of his close friend Robert Valentine, Frankfurter professed that Valentine ânot only sought, he not only found, he followed truth.â65×65. Id. at 79. At Justice Brandeisâs funeral, Frankfurter concluded his eulogy âby reciting several paragraphs from one of Brandeisâs favorite poems, John Bunyanâs Pilgrimâs Progress, about the death of âMr. Valiant-for-truth.ââ66×66. Id. at 383. In a Harvard Law Review tribute, Frankfurter praised the late Justice Jacksonâs âhabit of truth-seeking.â67×67. Id. at 601 (quoting Felix Frankfurter, Mr. Justice Jackson, 68 Harv. L. Rev. 937, 939 (1955)). And toward the end of his own life, Frankfurter gushed when he received that same high praise: he proudly shared the Times of Londonâs description of him as a âfighter for truthâ with former students.68×68. Id. at 5.
Seeking, finding, and following truth was Frankfurterâs guiding light, but his interpretive methodology was somewhat at odds with that ideal. Once Frankfurter had read Thayerâs The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law as a student, he ânever stopped quoting itâ the rest of his life.69×69. Id. at 21. Indeed, Frankfurter deemed Thayerâs work âthe most important single essayâ regarding constitutional law.70×70. Id.
But Thayerâs theory of judicial restraint was not motivated by a commitment to searching for, deducing, and then abiding by truth above all else. Thayer expressly stated that for judges deciding constitutional cases, âthe ultimate question is not what is the true meaning of the constitution.â71×71. Thayer, supra note 21, at 24. Rather, the question should be whether a legislative act is unconstitutional âbeyond a reasonable doubt.â72×72. Id. at 25. Thayer explained that when judges declare âthat the question for themâ is what is âclear beyond a reasonable doubt,â they lay bare âthat their decisions in support of the constitutionality of legislation do not . . . import their own opinion of the true construction of the constitution.â73×73. Id. (emphasis added). Therefore, according to Thayer, if judges impose a âbeyond a reasonable doubtâ burden of persuasion on parties attempting to invalidate legislation,74×74. For a trenchant analysis of how presumptions and burden-shifting frameworks from the law of evidence informed Thayerâs theory of judicial restraint, see Matthew J. Franck, James Bradley Thayer and the Presumption of Constitutionality: A Strange Posthumous Career, 8 Am. Pol. Thought 393, 406â09 (2019). they are not seeking, finding, and then applying true constitutional meaning as best they see it.
Frankfurter, the professed truth-seeker, relied on Thayerâs framework constantly as a Justice. Apart from the context of policing the separation of powers, which Frankfurter conceived of as âthe basic function of this Court,â75×75. Snyder, supra note 1, at 427. Frankfurter consistently granted Thayerian deference to democratic encroachments upon claims of individual rights. For example, in his majority opinion in Minersville School District v. Gobitis76×76. 310 U.S. 586 (1940). upholding the constitutionality of compulsory flag salutes for public school children, Frankfurter stated that unless âthe [governmentâs] transgression of constitutional liberty is too plain for argument,â its action is valid.77×77. Id. at 599. When left dissenting on that very same question three years later in West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette,78×78. 319 U.S. 624 (1943). Frankfurter stressed that âreasonable legislators could have taken the action which is before us.â79×79. Id. at 647 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting). And in a dissent he penned toward the very end of his judicial career, Frankfurter argued that the Court should only invalidate an act of Congress if it is âclearly outside the constitutional grant of power.â80×80. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 120 (1958) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting). Frankfurter also encouraged his colleagues to adopt his Thayerian approach. He counseled them that when an issue is âtough,â serious âdoubt must be resolved in favor of constitutionality.â81×81. Snyder, supra note 1, at 641.
These were not positive claims of constitutional truth. They were negative conclusions that the losing party had not overcome the weighty presumption of constitutionality. Frankfurterâs judicial restraint was premised more so on democratic presumptions than propositions about true constitutional meaning. His Thayerian restraint did not square perfectly with his commitment to valuing truth above all else.82×82. Perhaps the alleged tension can be resolved if Thayer and Frankfurterâs approach is framed as a truth claim about the meaning of the âjudicial powerâ under Article III. Thayerâs argument explicitly said as much. See Thayer, supra note 21, at 22 (labeling â[t]he judicial functionâ as âmerely that of fixing the outside border of reasonable legislative actionâ). But that still might pose a problem vis-Ă -vis Frankfurterâs commitment to objective truth. It expressly leaves open the possibility that the Constitution actually means one thing, but the judiciary will not enforce that meaning if it is not sufficiently obvious. Even after a difficult search for truth, having been supposedly found, the truth would not be followed. That does not align with Frankfurterâs mantra of honoring truth above all, nor does it square with his belief that â[t]he Supreme Court, like all human institutions, must earn reverence through the test of truth.â Frankfurter, supra note 52, at 932.
Thus, while Snyder commends âFrankfurterâs flexible approach to constitutional questions,â83×83. Snyder, supra note 1, at 559. that approach perhaps led him to forsake constitutional constraints. Frankfurter fondly quoted Thomas Jeffersonâs remark that âno statesman can plan for more than a generation ahead,â84×84. Id. at 495. and Frankfurter insisted that the Constitution is not âa doctrinaire document.â85×85. Id. at 391 (quoting Bridges v. California, 314 U.S. 252, 283 (1941) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting)). But in certain respects the Constitution is a doctrinaire document,86×86. See, e.g., U.S. Const. art. I, § 9, cl. 8 (expressly prohibiting titles of nobility). and the Constitutionâs Framers did plan for more than a generation ahead.87×87. See, e.g., id. art. V (laying out an amendment process). They premised their plan on their assessments of our enduring human nature,88×88. See, e.g., The Federalist No. 51, at 349 (James Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961) (âBut what is government itself but the greatest of all reflections on human nature?â). and they enacted that plan as the supreme law of the land.89×89. See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803) (deeming the Constitution âa superior, paramount law, unchangeable by ordinary meansâ). While Jefferson himself proposed redrafting the Constitution every nineteen years,90×90. Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Sept. 6, 1789), in 15 The Papers of Thomas Jefferson 392, 396 (Julian P. Boyd & William H. Gaines, Jr., eds., 1958). he nonetheless believed that its constraints must be strictly observed while it remained supreme law. The realities of human nature demanded no less: âIn questions of power let no more be said of confidence in man, but bind him down from mischief by the chains of the Constitution.â91×91. Snyder, supra note 1, at 552 (recounting advocate John W. Davisâs quotation of Jefferson during oral argument in Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579 (1952)). Neglecting to acknowledge such chains, at times Frankfurter stood by as Americans broke them.
Frankfurterâs belief in our capacity to govern ourselves should nonetheless resonate today. Frankfurter understood what many still refuse to grasp. The Supreme Court âisnât God.â92×92. Id. at 485. But nor are people angels, which is why we have constitutional government.93×93. See The Federalist No. 51, supra note 88, at 349 (James Madison) (âIf men were angels, no government would be necessary.â). Even as he inspires readers, Frankfurter should serve as a cautionary tale of the dangers of swinging to an opposite extreme â an extreme so skeptical of constraining constitutional meaning that it risks ultimately nudging us away from the enterprise of constitutionalism itself.94×94. This is not a theoretical risk. Some scholars have moved away from supporting a flexible, dynamic mode of constitutional interpretation toward embracing an explicit rejection of the very project of âconstitutionalism.â See, e.g., Ryan D. Doerfler & Samuel Moyn, Opinion, The Constitution Is Broken and Should Not Be Reclaimed, N.Y. Times (Aug. 19, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/08/19/opinion/liberals-constitution.html [https://perma.cc/CN37-SCTW].
To what extent Frankfurter was an imperfect interpreter of the Constitution is surely debatable, but as we argue with one another about American politics, judicial power, and the Constitution, his life counsels in favor of keeping the âopen mindsâ required to sustain an âopen society.â95×95. Snyder, supra note 1, at 542. That duty is particularly incumbent upon those of us lucky enough to attend institutions of higher education, which Frankfurter fondly described as âthe special guardians of the free pursuit of truth.â96×96. Id. at 400. It is essential to argue and debate with the very same commitment to seeking truth â whatever it may ultimately be â as Justice Felix Frankfurter so often did. But where he stopped, we should go further, still.
Â