Dormant Commerce Clause Note 137 Harv. L. Rev. 980

The Dormant Commerce Clause and Moral Complicity in a National Marketplace


Download

To stay experimentation in things social and economic is a grave responsibility. Denial of the right to experiment may be fraught with serious consequences to the Nation. It is one of the happy incidents of the federal system that a single courageous State may, if its citizens choose, serve as a laboratory; and try novel social and economic experiments without risk to the rest of the country.

— Justice Brandeis1

A theory of states as laboratories of democracy has long persisted as one of the fundamental tenets of American federalism. Yet, as Justice Brandeis intimated in his New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann2 dissent, judicial review enables courts to cut off state experimentation when it is at odds with federal constitutional principles or federal statutory pronouncements.3 One such federal principle — which has proven difficult to pin down4 — is the so-called “dormant,” or “negative,” commerce clause. Recent litigation and scholarship have invoked the dormant commerce clause as a limit on state ethical innovation, arguing that state regulations that impose unique compliance costs may need to yield to a uniform national market if they are based on a local moral interest that is at odds with the moral position of a majority of other states.5

Focusing on a recent case that raised this argument, National Pork Producers Council v. Ross,6 this Note argues that such a position is misguided. Even if the dormant commerce clause serves in some sense to establish a uniform national marketplace, there are important reasons to exempt states from participating in that marketplace where moral values are at issue. Rather than empowering courts to choose between competing moral positions by reviving a near-dead balancing test, the Court should limit the dormant commerce inquiry to the question of whether a sufficient moral interest exists. If so, the judicial role is fulfilled, though Congress remains free to reunite the marketplace through federal legislation if it chooses.

Part I of this Note provides the doctrinal background for the current dormant commerce clause debate. Part II describes National Pork. Though the suit largely focused on matters of extraterritoriality and state health interests, it also obliquely presented the question of how the dormant commerce clause should apply to “morals legislation” — here, legislation about the ethical treatment of animals — that runs the risk of dividing up a national economic market. The Court ultimately left the question of precisely how to balance moral interests against economic interests open, so Part III attempts to offer a possible resolution: that morality is entitled to solicitude under the dormant commerce inquiry based on states’ interests in avoiding complicity with unethical practices. Part IV briefly addresses a few counterarguments.

I. Doctrinal Background

The “dormant commerce clause” is a “negative implication”7 of the federal Constitution’s Commerce Clause, which says that Congress has the power “[t]o regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes.”8 Throughout its doctrinal history, the dormant commerce clause has engendered confusion and skepticism as the Court and scholars have struggled to derive sufficient principles to guide its application. Yet while the constitutional limits on morals legislation have been explored in detail in relation to other constitutional doctrines, the question of morality-based state legislation under the dormant commerce clause seems to be a relatively novel one.

A. Origins of the Dormant Commerce Doctrine

For two hundred years, the Supreme Court has interpreted the Commerce Clause not only as an affirmative grant of power to Congress but also as a restraint on the legislative authority of states. This conception of the clause first appeared, at least by implication, in Gibbons v. Ogden,9 a case in which the Court engaged in an extended discussion of the commerce power.10 Though the Court flirted with the conclusion that the commerce power was exclusive to Congress,11 it ultimately decided the matter based on the preemptive effect of a congressional enactment.12

Only a few years later, however, the Court more expressly acknowledged the operation of the clause as a restriction on state power. In Willson v. Black Bird Creek Marsh Co.,13 the Justices were confronted with a Commerce Clause challenge to the erection of a dam.14 While the Court concluded that the action did not offend the Constitution, it did so by stating: “We do not think that the act . . . can . . . be considered as repugnant to the power to regulate commerce in its dormant state.”15 The Court thus more clearly indicated that a state law could run afoul of Congress’s commerce power even if Congress had not exercised the power through a federal statute.

Many scholars have documented the Court’s ensuing misadventures in attempting to select an appropriate dormant commerce clause rule.16 In the mid-1800s, the Court adopted the Cooley v. Board of Wardens17 formulation.18 By the end of the nineteenth century, Leisy v. Hardin19 synthesized this “national/local”20 rule into the idea that:

[W]here the subject is national in its character, and admits and requires uniformity of regulation, affecting alike all the States, . . . Congress can alone act upon it . . . .  The absence of any law of Congress on the subject is equivalent to its declaration that commerce in that matter shall be free.21

Leisy’s “congressional silence” theory survived for decades, although it has since incurred the wrath of textualist jurists.22 Its federal uniformity component remains as a variation of the modern rule.23

Meanwhile, expansion of national trade throughout the 1800s mo­tivated the emergence of two additional dimensions of the doctrine: the antidiscrimination principle and the direct/indirect distinction. As to the former, the Court began noting that “attempt[s] to discriminate injuriously against the products of other States . . . [would operate as] an attempt to fetter commerce among the States.”24 The worry was that “all the evils of discriminating State legislation . . . which existed previous to the adoption of the Constitution, might follow”25 from expressly protectionist legislation — returning the United States to the very interstate turmoil that the new Constitution had sought to avoid.26

As to the latter, the dormant commerce doctrine paralleled the affirmative Commerce Clause doctrine27 in attempting to distinguish “direct” from “indirect” burdens on interstate commerce, where only the former violated the Constitution.28 The direct/indirect distinction was employed somewhat imprecisely29 and eventually fell by the wayside.30

B. The Modern Framework

Over time, the doctrine has convalesced around two general principles: the discrimination rule and the Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc.31 balancing test. As the Supreme Court recently reiterated:

State laws that discriminate against interstate commerce face “a virtually per se rule of invalidity.” State laws that “regulat[e] even-handedly to effectuate a legitimate local public interest . . . will be upheld unless the burden imposed on such commerce is clearly excessive in relation to the putative local benefits.”32

The first proposition in this formulation is a gloss on the discrimination rule. More precisely, the rule requires that:

[O]nce a state law is shown to discriminate against interstate commerce “either on its face or in practical effect,” the burden falls on the State to demonstrate both that the statute “serves a legitimate local purpose,” and that this purpose could not be served as well by available nondiscriminatory means.33

The second principle emerged after scholars34 and judges35 determined that ad hoc balancing might better capture the competing considerations at issue where a law did not have a discriminatory purpose or effect yet still significantly impacted interstate commerce.

The discrimination rule has enjoyed continued vitality. Perhaps given its relatively strong historical grounding,36 the Court has regularly repeated the holding that states must offer a legitimate interest other than protectionism to justify discriminating against interstate commerce;37 if a state cannot do so, its law will be struck down.38 Likewise, it has commonly found that a nondiscriminatory alternative is available to serve the state interest proffered.39 This pattern seemingly adheres to the proposal that Professor Donald Regan developed in a prominent 1986 article, that “in movement-of-goods cases what the Court should do and is doing is to prevent state protectionism. That and no more.”40

By contrast, the balancing test, while formally still alive and well,41 has largely fallen into disuse. From the outset, some members of the Court looked upon its adoption as an inappropriate expansion of the judicial role.42 Later, in Bendix Autolite Corp. v. Midwesco Enterprises, Inc.,43 Justice Scalia famously complained that though the test was “ordinarily called ‘balancing,’ . . . the scale analogy is not really appropriate, since the interests on both sides are incommensurate. It is more like judging whether a particular line is longer than a particular rock is heavy.”44 Since Justice Scalia’s Bendix concurrence, published two years after Regan’s article, “the Court has not struck down a single statute under the dormant Commerce Clause on grounds of burden.”45

Recently, however, a pair of scholars have sought to revitalize the balancing test. In Bibb Balancing,46 Professors Michael Knoll and Ruth Mason put forth a theoretical refinement on the Pike test. They argue that some burden analyses pertain to “single-state burdens, which arise from the application of a single state’s law alone,” and others pertain to “mismatch burdens, which arise from legal diversity” across state lines.47 The authors derive the theory from Bibb v. Navajo Freight Lines, Inc.,48 where the Court struck down an Illinois law regulating truck mudflaps in a manner that departed from the prevailing rule in other states.49

Acknowledging the Court’s inconsistent approach to balancing cases,50 as well as concerns about institutional competence,51 Knoll and Mason nonetheless believe balancing tests have an important place in dormant commerce doctrine.52 They criticize Regan’s theory as “insufficient,” because even nonprotectionist mismatch regulations “segment the national marketplace.”53 A focus on protectionist intent alone therefore could permit states to engage in “intentional regulatory spillovers,” so long as those spillovers are not effected specifically to protect in-state industry.54 This result, they contend, would be at odds with the principles underlying the Commerce Clause and dormant commerce doctrine.55 This Note addresses various animating aspects of their arguments as references for key theoretical points.

C. Judicial Review of Morals Legislation

A recent example of regulatory spillover highlights the novel intersection of “morals legislation” and dormant commerce. Knoll and Mason identify a particular California law as an “intentional regulatory spillover,” citing their view that it “intended to impose California stan­dards on hog farmers outside of California.”56 As the next Part will explain, moral or ethical views did play an important role in passage of the law, thus raising the question of how the dormant commerce rule should apply to morality-based legislation.

Before delving into a short survey of the Court’s approach to “morals legislation,” a brief word on what is meant by “morals legislation” or morality is necessary. In this Note, “morality” is used colloquially: morals legislation is that which reflects the acceptableness of acting in a certain way, not because there are health or safety implications to the behavior, but simply because the majority has deemed it to be “wrong.”

Some areas of Supreme Court jurisprudence have clearly addressed “morals legislation.” Perhaps most famously, Justice Kennedy’s majority opinion in Lawrence v. Texas57 announced — quoting from Justice Stevens’s dissent in Bowers v. Hardwick58 — that “the fact that the governing majority in a State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for upholding a law prohibiting the practice.”59 But in the wake of Justice Scalia’s infamous Lawrence dissent — in which he bemoaned “the end of all morals legislation”60 — many commentators observed that this exaggeration could not be descriptively accurate.61 Sure enough, the Lawrence majority author would write an opinion upholding a statute motivated by moral sentiment only a few years later.62

Other cases likewise indicate that public morality may be a legitimate basis for a law under appropriate circumstances. For example, the Court’s controlling obscenity rule reflects deference to the moral values of the relevant community.63 And Washington v. Glucksberg64 endorsed moral justifications in permitting Washington’s ban on assisted suicide, noting that “condemnation of suicide . . . [is a] consistent and enduring theme[] of our philosophical, legal and cultural heritage[].”65

As a matter of common sense, states can legitimately enact policies that primarily serve the moral well-being of their citizens. Multiple states restrict the sale or import of horse meat66 or the slaughter of horses for human consumption,67 and every state has at least one animal cruelty law.68 Taking horse meat as an example, that it is safe for human consumption suggests that state prohibitions reflect moral beliefs about which animals are appropriately used as food.69 Indeed, criminal laws might often be thought to express moral judgments about behaviors that are or are not acceptable in the relevant society.70

The important point is that certain limits exist on the scope of morals legislation — the Constitution itself being one such limit.71 Cases like Loving v. Virginia72 and Lawrence illustrate the fact that a state’s morality interests cannot be used to evade the values enshrined in the Equal Protection Clause and the Due Process Clause. Likewise, the First Amendment imposes restrictions on how governments can express moral views that burden speech, expression, and religious exercise.73

The issue addressed by this Note is whether and when the dormant commerce clause should operate as such a limit. The petitioners in the National Pork case took a stark position: that California’s moral interest was merely “illusory” in the context of the Pike test.74 Although ultimately the Justices did not closely analyze this question, the various opinions on the Pike issue hint at an approach the Court could take with regard to future morality-based “intentional regulatory spillovers.”

II. National Pork Producers Council v. Ross

National Pork concerned a California ballot initiative aimed at alleviating the suffering of farm animals raised for food. Assuming producers in other states abide by California’s requirements, the law will have the practical effect of altering production practices in other states, even if those states disagree with the standards. Because the view that California’s standards are morally preferable played a role in its passage, the law presented the question of whether and how courts should incorporate moral interests in dormant commerce clause analyses.

A. Proposition 12 and Its Detractors

California passed Proposition 12 on November 6, 2018, with 62.7% of the vote.75 The ballot measure, known as the Farm Animal Confinement Initiative, established certain minimum space requirements for veal-calf, breeding-pig, and egg-laying-hen enclosures.76 Proposition 12 was designed to address perceived shortcomings in its predecessor, 2008 California Proposition 2.77 First, Proposition 12 established minimum space measurements as opposed to only general guidelines based on animal behavior.78 Second, Proposition 12 aimed to prohibit the sale throughout the state of animal products from animals whose enclosures did not meet the designated standards.79 As a practical matter, this second alteration would exclude in-state sale of out-of-state animal products that did not meet California’s animal welfare standards.

Proposition 12 was based on multiple local interests.80 Most interestingly for the purposes of this Note, the law was animated by animal welfare concerns — which seem to be purely moral concerns. As the State asserted in its litigation briefs, “Californians plainly have an interest in whether local grocery stores and other retailers are contributing to a market that they view as immoral.”81 Likewise, the ballot initiative committee82 and various media commentators83 noted the ethical considerations at play in setting farm animal welfare standards.

The favorable public response did not dissuade meat-industry interest groups from mounting multiple challenges to the law.84 On October 4, 2019, the North American Meat Institute (NAMI), filed suit against then–California Attorney General Xavier Becerra and others in the Central District of California, alleging that Proposition 12 violated the Commerce Clause.85 The district court denied NAMI’s request for a preliminary injunction86 but permitted the suit to move past the motion to dismiss stage.87 A month later, the National Pork Producers Council and the American Farm Bureau Federation filed a similar suit in the Southern District of California,88 which was subsequently dismissed.89 The Ninth Circuit affirmed dismissal of the suit.90

Although the Supreme Court had previously denied NAMI’s petition for a writ of certiorari,91 the Court granted certiorari in National Pork Producers Council v. Ross in March 2022.92 The grant prompted commentators to wonder about the possible implications of a ruling in favor of the pork producers. Some commentators speculated that the National Pork case might impact laws attempting to restrict access to out-of-state abortions.93 Others raised the possibility that such a ruling might “cast doubt on state laws regulating fuel sources based on their life-cycle carbon emissions or prohibiting the use of certain chemicals in food packaging containers and materials.”94 Given the commonality of state law spillover effects, court watchers anticipated that the Court’s resolution of National Pork could have significant and far-reaching impacts.

B. The National Pork Opinion

At oral argument on October 11, 2022, the Justices gave little away about how the Court might decide the case.95 However, some moments in the argument fueled speculation about the possible gravity of the outcome.96 Justice Barrett, for example, asked whether California could prohibit products from companies that don’t require vaccination or fund gender-affirming surgery.97 Justice Kavanaugh raised hypotheticals related to immigrant laborers,98 minimum wages,99 and union membership.100 Justice Alito also pressed the union point.101 The Justices were concerned about economic Balkanization102 and retaliation103 that might result if states were more aggressive in using sale restrictions to influence out-of-state practices.

In the ultimate National Pork opinion, the Court flatly rejected the petitioners’ extraterritoriality arguments.104 But the Justices split over how to apply the Pike test.105 In line with the Court’s recent practice, the majority reiterated that “‘no clear line’ separates the Pike line of cases from [the Court’s] core antidiscrimination precedents.”106 Most of the time, discrimination is the deciding factor, and the Pike test simply helps “smoke out”107 a state’s protectionist purpose.

Where the Justices differed was in their view of judicial capacity to balance “economic costs . . . against noneconomic benefits”108 when an intent to discriminate is not in play. Writing for Justice Thomas, Justice Barrett, and himself, Justice Gorsuch expressed his concern that Pike should not be a “roving license for federal courts to decide what activities are appropriate for state and local government to undertake,”109 since “judges often are ‘not institutionally suited to draw reliable conclusions of the kind that would be necessary . . . to satisfy [the] Pike’ test.”110 He urged that the questions raised were better directed to Congress111 — a suggestion promptly taken up by Senator Roger Marshall of Kansas, who introduced the Ending Agricultural Trade Suppression (EATS) Act112 in the Senate on June 15, 2023. Justice Gorsuch went on — writing for Justices Thomas, Sotomayor, and Kagan — to say that, in any case, the petitioners had failed to establish that Proposition 12 imposed “a sufficient burden . . . to warrant further scrutiny.”113

But six of the nine Justices felt more confident in the judicial capacity for balancing seemingly incommensurate interests. In her partial concurrence, which was joined by Justice Kagan, Justice Sotomayor “acknowlfedge[d] that the inquiry is difficult and delicate, and [that] federal courts are well advised to approach the matter with caution.”114 But she agreed with Chief Justice Roberts “that courts generally are able to weigh disparate burdens and benefits.”115 For his part, Chief Justice Roberts — writing for Justices Alito, Kavanaugh, and Jackson — explained that “sometimes there is no avoiding the need to weigh seemingly incommensurable values.”116 Indeed, the Court does so frequently under First and Fourth Amendment doctrine.117

The National Pork opinion left the controversy over state moral interests at that higher level of abstraction. Despite the assertion that courts are equipped to compare economic costs against noneconomic benefits, the six Justices holding that position did not further explicate how lower court judges should resolve the particular problem presented: whether a moral benefit was weighty enough to take precedence over an out-of-state seller’s access to the state market. In the next Part, this Note sketches a possible compromise approach for dormant commerce clause inquiries into morally motivated legislation, inspired by analogy to prior judicial and legislative treatment of conscience concerns.

III. A Dormant Commerce Framework for State Moral Motives

Anxieties about the appropriateness of the judiciary weighing seemingly incommensurate interests are perhaps particularly acute when it comes to morality. Though “[t]he dormant commerce clause . . . seems to embody some notion of judicial protection for out-of-state interests,”118 Regan aptly points out that a broad understanding of the Pike balancing test would likely result in a “homogenization of values.”119 Yet freedom of conscience — the right to decide on one’s own ethical and moral values — has a long and storied history in American law.

Judicial opinions are littered with language celebrating the liberty interest in being able to act on conscience. In Wallace v. Jaffree,120 a school prayer case, Justice Stevens wrote that “the individual’s freedom of conscience [is] the central liberty that unifies the various Clauses in the First Amendment.”121 Chief Justice Hughes’s dissent in United States v. Macintosh,122 a conscientious objection case, noted the Court’s “regard from the beginning for freedom of conscience.”123 And Justice Roberts in Cantwell v. Connecticut124 said that “[f]reedom of conscience . . . cannot be restricted by law.”125

Nor is this history unique to the judiciary. Until Employment Division v. Smith,126 the Court applied strict scrutiny to laws that “force[d individuals] to choose between”127 following their religious beliefs or receiving government benefits.128 When Smith departed from the Sherbert-Yoder test, Congress reacted by passing the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993129 (RFRA). RFRA criticized Smith’s “virtual[] eliminat[ion of] the requirement that the government justify burdens on religious exercise imposed by laws neutral toward religion,”130 and reimposed strict scrutiny.131 Worries about burdening religious belief and matters of conscience became widespread in the context of the abortion debate and conscientious objection.132

In line with ideals of liberal neutrality,133 then, the federal government has historically been solicitous to individuals’ or corporations’ worries about complicity in conduct they view as immoral. Such solicitude makes sense where there are concerns about judges directly assessing the validity of moral beliefs — and perhaps substituting their own views.134 For example, Professor Stephen Gottlieb previously concluded that the conservatives on the Rehnquist Court had “substituted more personal views of a just world”135 to impose a particular vision of traditional morality on the country through constitutional law. Other scholars have concluded that liberal Justices have similarly engaged in moral “overreach[]” and failed to engage in “a proper neutrality as between divergent perspectives.”136 Yet, to borrow the words of Professor Samuel Stumpf, “the Court is conscious of its restricted sphere in [the American] system of government.”137 As neutral arbiters (at least in theory), judges generally should not refer to their own moral beliefs to resolve disputes. Accordingly, the Court has tended to avoid directly assessing the validity of beliefs or values, instead reviewing only the sincerity with which the belief appears to be held.138

A kind of conscience or complicity worry is how California has characterized its citizens’ interest in Proposition 12: the law embodies California voters’ desire not to “contribut[e] to a market that they view as immoral.”139 If the dormant commerce clause provides grounds for too easily striking down this kind of morality law, it will force the state to participate in conduct it finds ethically repugnant. This suggests that freedom of conscience and religion doctrines might offer a fruitful jumping-off point for evaluating morality justifications under the dormant commerce clause. Of course, analogous treatment raises two important questions: Can a state express a complicity interest? And if it can, how might judges discern whether the stated complicity concern is legitimate?

A. Can a State Be “Complicit”?

There are two ways in which a state’s law may invoke a complicity interest. First, and most straightforwardly, states may enact laws based on an interest in preventing individual residents from being complicit in wrongdoing. Prohibitions on “indirect wrongdoing”140 have long been embodied in law. A classic example is conspiracy, which enables an individual to “be held responsible . . . regardless of whether or not he directly participated in the act.”141 Hearkening back to an earlier example used in this Note, laws banning production or sale of horse meat for human consumption similarly aim to prevent individual producers or sellers from being complicit in a wrong — regardless of whether that individual shares the moral sentiment invoked.

Second, there is an argument to be made that a state, as a collective entity, can itself be complicit in wrongdoing.142 Recently, much organizing effort has been expended on pressuring collective entities, whether corporate,143 governmental,144 or social145 in form, to take actions that are likely to alleviate wrongs. What makes this kind of organizing appropriate is that these groups have coordinated structures for policymaking and enforcement.146 As a result, the whole of the collective is able to carry out wrongs that would not be possible for an individual member to execute alone. This feature, which Professor Peter French refers to as “conglomerate collectivity,”147 means that the collective entity can be a moral agent. Where that collective has a moral obligation to prevent some harm and fails to do so, it is morally blameworthy for the failure.148

Though not significantly theorized in the realm of domestic constitutional law, problems of state complicity have been analyzed in the context of international law and human rights. For example, an Annual Review of Political Science article recently argued that “[s]tates employing privilege violence are more accurately viewed not as weak but as complicit in the violence that binds their governing system.”149 And Professor Miles Jackson explored state complicity under international law in a recently published book.150

In short, it seems reasonable to think that a state can invoke a complicity interest — on behalf of either itself or its individual citizens — in passing a morally motivated law. The question then becomes: How can courts discern whether a proffered complicity law should be permitted? This is where the analogy to freedom of conscience and freedom of religion doctrine comes into play.

B. When Is a State “Complicit”?

The Justices expressed concern about state abuse of morality claims at oral argument for National Pork,151 and courts do inquire into legislative motive in other areas of constitutional jurisprudence.152 Accordingly, courts may want to examine state conscience laws for whether the complicity motive is valid.

Fortunately, there is a significant body of philosophical and religious literature that may help draw out what, specifically, “complicity” entails.153 Essentially, “secondary agents” — those “whose actions do not constitute the principal wrongdoing but are part of a causal chain leading to it”154 — can engage in “secondary wrongdoing.”155 Chiara Lepora and Professor Robert Goodin explain that:

How morally blameworthy an act of complicity is is a function of four things: the moral badness of the principal wrongdoing; whether . . . the secondary agent crosses the threshold of moral responsibility for having contributed to it; how much of a contribution his act made (or might make) to the principal wrongdoing; and the extent to which the secondary agent shares the purposes of the principal wrongdoer.156

A simplified assessment using this formulation could help answer the question of whether a law like California’s is reasonably based on a concern about moral complicity.157

The first factor gets at the truth of whether a certain act is in fact morally bad, as well as how bad it is in comparison to other moral wrongs. By analogy to other conscience and religion cases, courts should be deferential to states on this factor, for “‘[m]en may believe what they cannot prove.’ . . . [C]ourts . . . are not free to reject beliefs because they consider them ‘incomprehensible.’”158 Instead, the question should be whether the moral or religious belief is sincere or genuine,159 looking at indicators such as legislative history and internal consistency.

The remaining factors, though, are compatible with further probing. For purposes of this Note, it is not necessary to delve deeply into the intricacies of the different factors or how specifically they should be evaluated. It is enough to say that if a state seems to sincerely hold the belief that a particular action is morally wrong, and if there is a voluntary and knowing causal relationship between certain conduct and the wrongful act, the baseline for moral complicity has likely been met. A state would then have reasonable — not illusory — grounds for adopting a conscience law that cuts off the complicity.

C. Complicity and the Pike Balance

Concluding that the state’s interest is genuine does not terminate the inquiry. There is still the question of how that noneconomic interest weighs against the economic interests apparently embodied in the dormant commerce clause. Here the Court has left open another point: whether the Commerce Clause specifically constitutionalizes a free market beyond simply ensuring that states do not intentionally discriminate against out-of-state economic interests.

Chief Justice Roberts’s National Pork opinion alluded that it might, citing H.P. Hood & Sons, Inc. v. Du Mond160 for the proposition that the U.S. system encourages production by assuring “every farmer and every craftsman . . . that he will have free access to every market in the Nation.”161 Briefing by Knoll and Mason and by the National Pork petitioners took the same tack, arguing that “split[ting] the national marketplace along state boundaries”162 amounts to precisely the economic Balkanization that the dormant commerce clause aims to avoid163 and that California’s law “invite[s] ‘tit-for-tat state regulatory conflict’ and threaten[s] to transform our ‘integrated national market into a patchwork of regulatory regions.’”164 The National Pork briefing drew upon broad language from extraterritoriality cases165 to suggest this substantive requirement of a uniform market.166

But there are reasons to doubt that the Commerce Clause stands for such a far-reaching economic position. For one thing, it is in tension with the commitment to federalism embodied in the Tenth Amendment.167 Because that amendment has been interpreted to preserve states’ ex­pansive “police powers” over their internal regulations,168 the practical reality is that the national marketplace frequently does look like a patchwork. A technology company based in California today, for example, must comply with differing privacy regulations in Virginia169 and Colorado170 if it wishes to do business in those states. As a result, various Justices have expressed skepticism that the brief text of the Commerce Clause should be read to stringently limit states.171

But even supposing the dormant commerce clause did stand for an underlying “uniform national regulation” principle, the Pike test contemplates departure from the market baseline when the local state interest is sufficiently weighty.172 Knoll and Mason highlighted this point when they said: “The dormant Commerce Clause does not require national uniformity in all regulation. Instead, it requires that states imposing regulations that generate significant burdens on interstate commerce because those regulations differ from other states’ regulations must have sufficient reasons to justify those burdens.”173 Health and safety interests are frequently sufficient to justify burdens on the right of access to a state market.174 Federal solicitude for freedom of conscience suggests that morality interests should be, too — particularly given that moral belief is not susceptible to validity evaluations like those that resolved the Bibb case.175 Still, this is not to say that states are unequivocally entitled to their so-called morality laws.

IV. When Morals Legislation Is Not Morals Legislation

The implications of this argument may raise a number of concerns. First, perhaps states might attempt to use morality as a get-out-of-commerce-free card, labeling issues that really amount to policy preferences as “moral” to limit judicial review. Second, perhaps states could use a claimed moral motivation as cover for retaliatory activity. Third, perhaps broad power to enact legislation based on complicity concerns will further enable states to pass laws facilitating discrimination or restricting access to abortion. Finally, perhaps large states like California might now be able to “force other States to regulate in accordance with . . . idiosyncratic state demands,”176 effectively imposing on smaller states what those states perceive to be ethically repugnant requirements.

The proposed approach leaves courts with options for addressing these worries. Following in the footsteps of Regan’s earlier theory, the approach permits courts to consider whether the legislation is primarily retaliatory, protectionist, or coercive.177 A simplified version of this kind of case can be illustrated using Justice Alito’s “right to work” example during the National Pork oral argument.178 If a state banned sales of products created by people who lacked a “right to work,” the framing of the ban in terms of another state’s statutory rights looks more like policy coercion — raising worries of infringement on state autonomy — than like an ethical concern. Likewise, the complicity inquiry could investigate whether the enacting state’s rule is germane enough to the barred product or practice to create a risk of complicity; if not, the dormant commerce clause might pose a barrier. This analysis might resemble the Spending Clause rule: if the banned conduct is not clearly related to the product targeted by the legislation, the law would be an illegitimate attempt to exercise the conscience exception.179 For example, with Proposition 12, the poorly treated animal literally is the banned product.180 On the other hand, states likely cannot leverage regulations of consumer products against companies that also provide access to abortion or gender-affirming care, because those services are not component parts of the companies’ products.

In short, the concern in these policy coercion and retaliation cases is not the fact of the regulatory mismatch; rather, it is about intent. Knoll and Mason implicitly accept this point: their dissatisfaction with California’s law is that it “suppl[ies] the states with a roadmap”181 for segmenting the market and engaging in “severe intentional regulatory spillovers.”182 Intentional regulatory spillovers are state laws that “can be understood as intended to impose [the enacting state’s] standards on [actors] outside of [that state].”183 This framing presumes an illegitimate motive. But if states adopt laws based on reasonable concerns about complicity, the intent is not one of infringing on autonomy, even if the practical result is changed practices in other states whose producers wish to preserve access to the enacting state’s market.

The more difficult concern to address is that judicial deference to laws based on complicity might enable states to enact legislation further restricting abortion or enabling discrimination. After all, these dormant commerce limits on “morals legislation” would apply equally to all states and policies, regardless of political valence. This Note does not advocate gerrymandering constitutional doctrine to achieve certain policy goals and defeat others. Therefore, to the extent that a judge concluded that a policy was motivated by sincere moral belief, the policy would be entitled to this more deferential standard under the dormant commerce clause. One kind of response to this concern — albeit one that is not entirely satisfying — is that perhaps the dormant commerce doctrine is not the appropriate vehicle for challenging these types of laws. That is to say: even if a state is concerned about complicity of some kind, any law it passes must comport with the First Amendment,184 the Due Process Clause,185 and the Equal Protection Clause.186 Thus, majoritarian judgments still cannot impose a particular religious belief system statewide, they will be hard-pressed to justify categorization based on protected identities, and they cannot invade too far into the realm of privacy protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.

Finally, state-level complicity laws feel different from what Professors Douglas NeJaime and Reva Siegel have previously described as use of religious exemptions to “preserve traditional morality.”187 They explain that these exemptions arose as an alternative to “entrench[ing] traditional morality through laws of general application” once the movement no longer commanded a political majority.188 But here there is no federal law of general application from which states seek exception; instead, there is only a soft presumption of regulatory uniformity for interstate commerce that health and safety concerns frequently rebut.

In the case of Proposition 12, the pork producers sought to “resist legal settlement of conflict”189 by constructing a tool for ongoing contestation of social norms that have won out in the political process of the relevant state.190 Proclaiming that they simply hold a different moral view from California’s,191 the pork producers believed that the opposing moral viewpoints should cancel out.192 But the crucial point is that other states and producers outside California need not make any changes if they are morally opposed to California’s position. They can simply decline to distribute products to California.193 The changes must be made only if the producers conclude that access to the market is worth transitioning to the production format required.194

The backstop for state ethical experimentation is Congress,195 not the courts. Courts are reasonably well equipped to consider legislative motivation, helping to explain the general agreement about the dormant commerce clause’s discrimination principle.196 When it comes to the types of mismatch regulations that the pork producers targeted,197 courts can apply the same skillset to ascertain whether a given regulation is based on a genuine concern about complicity and moral responsibility. But courts should not be in a position to choose between different substantive moral positions based on an inchoate balancing test. Instead, the question should be whether the state has a genuine and well-founded conscience concern underlying its law.

Conclusion

One beauty — and challenge — of federalism is that states may deviate ethically from one another. In resolving the petitioners’ dormant commerce clause challenge, the National Pork Court stopped short of providing guidance to lower courts on how, precisely, to incorporate moral interests into a dormant commerce analysis. Still, six of the Justices agreed that judges need not decline to balance incommensurate interests. This Note suggests that concerns about judges freely balancing moral interests against economic ones are valid and that courts could take inspiration from freedom of conscience and freedom of religion rules to limit the scope of a dormant commerce clause inquiry.

Footnotes
  1. ^ New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U.S. 262, 311 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting).

    Return to citation ^
  2. ^ 285 U.S. 262.

    Return to citation ^
  3. ^ Id. at 311 (Brandeis, J., dissenting).

    Return to citation ^
  4. ^ See, e.g., Brannon P. Denning, Reconstructing the Dormant Commerce Clause Doctrine, 50 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 417, 417 (2008) (discussing the allegations of “incoherence and unpredictability” that have historically been lodged at the Supreme Court’s dormant commerce doctrine).

    Return to citation ^
  5. ^ See, e.g., Brief for Petitioners at 27, Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (2023) (No. 21-468) (quoting S. Pac. Co. v. Arizona ex rel. Sullivan, 325 U.S. 761, 767 n.2 (1945)); Michael S. Knoll & Ruth Mason, Bibb Balancing: Regulatory Mismatches Under the Dormant Commerce Clause, 91 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 1, 76 & n.350 (2023).

    Return to citation ^
  6. ^ 143 S. Ct. 1142.

    Return to citation ^
  7. ^ Dep’t of Revenue v. Davis, 553 U.S. 328, 337 (2008).

    Return to citation ^
  8. ^ U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 3.

    Return to citation ^
  9. ^ 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1 (1824).

    Return to citation ^
  10. ^ See id. at 186–239.

    Return to citation ^
  11. ^ See id. at 199–200 (rejecting the proffered analogy to the power of taxation, because “[w]hen . . . each government exercises the power of taxation, neither is exercising the power of the other. But, when a State proceeds to regulate commerce . . . among the several States, it is exercising the very power that is granted to Congress,” id. at 199).

    Return to citation ^
  12. ^ Id. at 221.

    Return to citation ^
  13. ^ 27 U.S. (2 Pet.) 245 (1829).

    Return to citation ^
  14. ^ Id. at 245–46.

    Return to citation ^
  15. ^ Id. at 252.

    Return to citation ^
  16. ^ See, e.g., David P. Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme Court: The First Hundred Years, 1789–1888, at 229–30 (1985) (describing the Taney Court’s efforts to clarify the dormant commerce clause doctrine as “submerg[ing] the unhappy reader in a torrent of verbiage . . . without providing any meaningful guidance,” id. at 230, which resulted in “almost total [doctrinal] incoherence,” id. at 229–30); Denning, supra note 4, at 433–34 (noting that the License Cases “not only settled nothing, but they actually sowed more confusion,” id. at 433, and that the Passenger Cases “continued the unedifying airing of multiple points of view,” id. at 434).

    Return to citation ^
  17. ^ 53 U.S. (12 How.) 299 (1852).

    Return to citation ^
  18. ^ Cooley indicated that some subjects of commerce regulation “imperatively demand[] a single uniform rule . . . and some . . . imperatively demand[] that diversity, which alone can meet the local necessities of navigation.” Id. at 319.

    Return to citation ^
  19. ^ 135 U.S. 100 (1890).

    Return to citation ^
  20. ^ Denning, supra note 4, at 438; see also id. at 435–36.

    Return to citation ^
  21. ^ Leisy, 135 U.S. at 119.

    Return to citation ^
  22. ^ See, e.g., Camps Newfound/Owatonna, Inc. v. Town of Harrison, 520 U.S. 564, 615 (1997) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (“To the extent that the ‘pre-emption-by-silence’ rationale ever made sense, it, too, has long since been rejected by this Court in virtually every analogous area of the law.”).

    Return to citation ^
  23. ^ See, e.g., Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 6 F.4th 1021, 1031 (9th Cir. 2021) (indicating that the principle that “‘state regulation of activities that are inherently national or require a uniform system of regulation’ violates the dormant Commerce Clause” can be “deemed a ‘variation’ of the two primary principles of the dormant Commerce Clause” (quoting Rosenblatt v. City of Santa Monica, 940 F.3d 439, 452 (9th Cir. 2019)) (citing South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 138 S. Ct. 2080, 2090–91 (2018))), aff’d, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (2023).

    Return to citation ^
  24. ^ Woodruff v. Parham, 75 U.S. (8 Wall.) 123, 140 (1869).

    Return to citation ^
  25. ^ Welton v. Missouri, 91 U.S. 275, 281 (1876).

    Return to citation ^
  26. ^ Barry Friedman & Daniel T. Deacon, A Course Unbroken: The Constitutional Legitimacy of the Dormant Commerce Clause, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1877, 1886–93 (2011) (discussing the issue of interstate and retaliatory tariffs in the wake of the Revolutionary War); see also Hughes v. Oklahoma, 441 U.S. 322, 325–26 (1979) (“[T]he Commerce Clause . . . reflected a central concern of the Framers that was an immediate reason for calling the Constitutional Convention: the conviction that in order to succeed, the new Union would have to avoid the tendencies toward economic Balkanization that had plagued relations among the Colonies and later among the States under the Articles of Confederation.” (citing H.P. Hood & Sons, Inc. v. Du Mond, 336 U.S. 525, 533–34 (1949))).

    Return to citation ^
  27. ^ See Barry Cushman, Formalism and Realism in Commerce Clause Jurisprudence, 67 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1089, 1126 (2000) (“Affirmative Commerce Clause doctrine during this period, then, was the flip side of the Court’s dormant Commerce Clause jurisprudence.”).

    Return to citation ^
  28. ^ Smith v. Alabama, 124 U.S. 465, 482–83 (1888) (finding a statute valid “so far as it affects transactions of commerce among the States . . . only indirectly, incidentally, and remotely, and not so as to burden or impede them,” id. at 482).

    Return to citation ^
  29. ^ Cushman, supra note 27, at 1114–16 (explaining that the distinction sometimes indicated that the subject of regulation did not fall within Congress’s commerce power and other times suggested that it could be regulated by Congress, but that the state’s regulation affected interstate commerce without attempting to directly regulate it).

    Return to citation ^
  30. ^ Denning, supra note 4, at 440. A preview to its demise appeared in Di Santo v. Pennsylvania, 273 U.S. 34 (1927), overruled by California v. Thompson, 313 U.S. 109 (1941), where Justice Stone in dissent noted that “the traditional test of the limit of state action by inquiring whether the interference with commerce is direct or indirect seems to me too mechanical, too uncertain in its application, and too remote from actualities, to be of value.” Id. at 44 (Stone, J., dissenting).

    Return to citation ^
  31. ^ 397 U.S. 137 (1970).

    Return to citation ^
  32. ^ South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 138 S. Ct. 2080, 2091 (2018) (citation omitted) (quoting Granholm v. Heald, 544 U.S. 460, 476 (2005); Pike, 397 U.S. at 142) (citing S. Pac. Co. v. Arizona ex rel. Sullivan, 325 U.S. 761, 779 (1945)).

    Return to citation ^
  33. ^ Maine v. Taylor, 477 U.S. 131, 138 (1986) (quoting Hughes v. Oklahoma, 441 U.S. 322, 336 (1979)) (citing Sporhase v. Nebraska ex rel. Douglas, 458 U.S. 941, 957 (1982); Hunt v. Wash. State Apple Advert. Comm’n, 432 U.S. 333, 353 (1977); Dean Milk Co. v. City of Madison, 340 U.S. 349, 354 (1951)).

    Return to citation ^
  34. ^ E.g., John B. Sholley, The Negative Implications of the Commerce Clause, 3 U. Chi. L. Rev. 556, 592 (1936); Noel T. Dowling, Interstate Commerce and State Power, 27 Va. L. Rev. 1, 19–28 (1940).

    Return to citation ^
  35. ^ See supra note 30 (discussing Justice Stone’s characterization of the earlier formulations as “too mechanical”); see also S. Pac. Co., 325 U.S. at 770–71 (“Hence the matters for ultimate determination here are . . . whether the relative weights of the state and national interests involved are such as to make inapplicable the rule . . . that the free flow of interstate commerce . . . [is] safeguarded by the commerce clause from state interference . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  36. ^ See supra notes 24–26 and accompanying text.

    Return to citation ^
  37. ^ E.g., New Energy Co. v. Limbach, 486 U.S. 269, 274 (1988) (“Thus, state statutes that clearly discriminate against interstate commerce are routinely struck down . . . unless the discrimination is demonstrably justified by a valid factor unrelated to economic protectionism.” (citations omitted) (citing Sporhase, 458 U.S. 941; Lewis v. BT Inv. Managers, Inc., 447 U.S. 27 (1980); Dean Milk Co., 340 U.S. 349; Maine v. Taylor, 477 U.S. 131 (1986))); see also C & A Carbone, Inc. v. Town of Clarkstown, 511 U.S. 383, 402 (1994) (O’Connor, J., concurring in the judgment) (citing Wyoming v. Oklahoma, 502 U.S. 437, 454 (1992); Taylor, 477 U.S. at 138).

    Return to citation ^
  38. ^ See Wyoming v. Oklahoma, 502 U.S. at 454–55 (“Indeed, when the state statute amounts to simple economic protectionism, a ‘virtually per se rule of invalidity’ has applied.” (quoting City of Philadelphia v. New Jersey, 437 U.S. 617, 624 (1978))).

    Return to citation ^
  39. ^ C & A Carbone, 511 U.S. at 393 (“Here Clarkstown has any number of nondiscriminatory alternatives . . . .”); Chem. Waste Mgmt., Inc. v. Hunt, 504 U.S. 334, 344–45 (1992) (“Less discriminatory alternatives, however, are available to alleviate this concern . . . .”); Dean Milk Co., 340 U.S. at 354 (“It appears that reasonable and adequate alternatives are available.”).

    Return to citation ^
  40. ^ Donald H. Regan, The Supreme Court and State Protectionism: Making Sense of the Dormant Commerce Clause, 84 Mich. L. Rev. 1091, 1099 (1986).

    Return to citation ^
  41. ^ See South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 138 S. Ct. 2080, 2091 (2018).

    Return to citation ^
  42. ^ S. Pac. Co. v. Arizona ex rel. Sullivan, 325 U.S. 761, 788 (1945) (Black, J., dissenting) (accusing the Court of acting as a “super-legislature”).

    Return to citation ^
  43. ^ 486 U.S. 888 (1988).

    Return to citation ^
  44. ^ Id. at 897 (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (quoting Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc., 397 U.S. 137, 142 (1970)).

    Return to citation ^
  45. ^ See Daniel Francis, The Decline of the Dormant Commerce Clause, 94 Denv. L. Rev. 255, 301 (2017); see also id. at 292. Indeed, Professor Daniel Francis argues that Regan hastened the Pike test’s decline. Id. at 283 (quoting CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of Am., 481 U.S. 69, 87 (1987)).

    Return to citation ^
  46. ^ Knoll & Mason, supra note 5.

    Return to citation ^
  47. ^ Id. at 1.

    Return to citation ^
  48. ^ 359 U.S. 520 (1959).

    Return to citation ^
  49. ^ Id. at 530.

    Return to citation ^
  50. ^ Knoll & Mason, supra note 5, at 9.

    Return to citation ^
  51. ^ E.g., id. (citing S.C. State Highway Dep’t v. Barnwell Bros., 303 U.S. 177, 195–96 (1938)).

    Return to citation ^
  52. ^ See id. at 8–9.

    Return to citation ^
  53. ^ Id. at 75.

    Return to citation ^
  54. ^ Id. at 76.

    Return to citation ^
  55. ^ Id.

    Return to citation ^
  56. ^ Id. n.350.

    Return to citation ^
  57. ^ 539 U.S. 558 (2003).

    Return to citation ^
  58. ^ 478 U.S. 186 (1986).

    Return to citation ^
  59. ^ Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 577 (quoting Bowers, 478 U.S. at 216 (Stevens, J., dissenting)).

    Return to citation ^
  60. ^ Id. at 599 (Scalia, J., dissenting).

    Return to citation ^
  61. ^ E.g., Peter de Marneffe, Sexual Freedom and Impersonal Value, 7 Crim. L. & Phil. 495, 511 (2013) (“Furthermore, even if the Lawrence decision did rest on the general principle that majority disapproval cannot justify any sexual restrictions, this principle would still not decree the end of all morals legislation . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  62. ^ See Gonzales v. Carhart, 550 U.S. 124, 158 (2007) (Kennedy, J.) (“Congress could nonetheless conclude that the type of abortion proscribed by the Act requires specific regulation because it implicates additional ethical and moral concerns that justify a special prohibition.”).

    Return to citation ^
  63. ^ See Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 24 (1973) (quoting Kois v. Wisconsin, 408 U.S. 229, 230 (1972)) (describing a three-part test that considers whether a community member would find the depiction “patently offensive” or appealing to “the prurient interest”).

    Return to citation ^
  64. ^ 521 U.S. 702 (1997).

    Return to citation ^
  65. ^ Id. at 711 (citing Thomas J. Marzen et al., Suicide: A Constitutional Right?, 24 Duq. L. Rev. 1, 17–56 (1985); N.Y. State Task Force on Life & the L., When Death Is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context 77–82 (1994)).

    Return to citation ^
  66. ^ E.g., Conn. Gen. Stat. § 21a-22 (2023); Minn. Stat. Ann. § 31.621 (2022).

    Return to citation ^
  67. ^ E.g., 225 Ill. Comp. Stat. § 635/1.5(a) (2022); N.J. Stat. Ann. § 4:22-25.5 (West 1998); Cal. Penal Code § 598c (2011).

    Return to citation ^
  68. ^ Laws that Protect Animals, Animal Legal Def. Fund, https://aldf.org/article/laws-that-protect-animals [https://perma.cc/Q9WJ-L7AJ] (“Each of the 50 states now has a felony animal cruelty law on the books. Each state determines what constitutes cruelty . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  69. ^ See Susanna Forrest, The Troubled History of Horse Meat in America, The Atlantic (June 8, 2017), https://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2017/06/horse-meat/529665 [https://perma.cc/WE37-5TDB].

    Return to citation ^
  70. ^ See, e.g., Steven Shavell, Law Versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct, 4 Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 227, 228 (2002) (“However, law and morality work together to control a vast range of behavior; notably, most crimes and torts are not only legally sanctionable but are also thought immoral . . . .”); Richard C. Fuller, Morals and the Criminal Law, 32 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 624, 624 (1942) (“Sociologically speaking, . . . a criminal statute is simply the formal embodiment of someone’s moral values (usually the group dominant in political authority) in an official edict . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  71. ^ To paraphrase Professor Jamal Greene, the real question regarding morals legislation is: When is it too burdensome or unjustifiable? See Jamal Greene, The Supreme Court, 2017 Term — Foreword: Rights as Trumps?, 132 Harv. L. Rev. 28, 62 (2018).

    Return to citation ^
  72. ^ 388 U.S. 1 (1967).

    Return to citation ^
  73. ^ E.g., United States v. Stevens, 559 U.S. 460, 469 (2010) (“As the Government notes, the prohibition of animal cruelty itself has a long history in American law, starting with the early settlement of the Colonies. But we are unaware of any similar tradition excluding depictions of animal cruelty from ‘the freedom of speech’ codified in the First Amendment, and the Government points us to none.” (citations omitted)); see also Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49, 57 (1973).

    Return to citation ^
  74. ^ Brief for Petitioners, supra note 5, at 44.

    Return to citation ^
  75. ^ Sec’y of State Alex Padilla, Statement of Vote: November 6, 2018 General Election 16 (2018), https://elections.cdn.sos.ca.gov/sov/2018-general/sov/2018-complete-sov.pdf [https://perma.cc/R9AZ-M7C7].

    Return to citation ^
  76. ^ Cal. Proposition 12: Establishes New Standards for Confinement of Specified Farm Animals; Bans Sale of Noncomplying Products. Initiative Statute. (2018), https://repository.uclawsf.edu/ca_ballot_props/1377 [https://perma.cc/TW9H-XDAQ].

    Return to citation ^
  77. ^ Cal. Proposition 2: Standards for Confining Farm Animals. Initiative Statute. (2008), https://repository.uclawsf.edu/ca_ballot_props/1282 [https://perma.cc/7RBF-PLHM]; see also Sara Amundson, Voters Must Be Heard on California’s Proposition 12, Humane Soc’y Legis. Fund (Dec. 1, 2021), https://hslf.org/blog/2021/12/voters-must-be-heard-californias-proposition-12 [https://perma.cc/VWJ5-4465] (“Proposition 12 built on another ballot measure approved by California voters in 2008, Proposition 2 . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  78. ^ Cal. Health & Safety Code § 25991(e) (West 2010 & Supp. 2023).

    Return to citation ^
  79. ^ Id. § 25990(b).

    Return to citation ^
  80. ^ In addition to the moral interest, health and safety concerns also animated Proposition 12. See Brief of American Public Health Ass’n et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of Respondents at 6–7, Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (2023) (No. 21-468).

    Return to citation ^
  81. ^ Brief for the State Respondents at 45, Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (No. 21-468) (emphasis added).

    Return to citation ^
  82. ^ See Campaign Overview, Yes on 12, https://web.archive.org/web/20230404083438/https://preventcrueltyca.com/campaign-overview.html [https://perma.cc/J9T7-AE8X].

    Return to citation ^
  83. ^ See, e.g., Jan Dutkiewicz & Jeff Sebo, The Legal Fight over California’s Ban on Cruel Animal Cages Will Have National Repercussions, New Republic (June 29, 2022), https://www.newrepublic.com/article/166932/legal-fight-californias-prop-12-animal-rights [https://perma.cc/J8H8-Z2H4].

    Return to citation ^
  84. ^ The Iowa Pork Producers Association even attempted to sue the California officials in Iowa state court; upon removal to federal court, the suit was promptly dismissed. Iowa Pork Producers Ass’n v. Bonta, No. 21-CV-3018, 2021 WL 4465968, at *3, *12 (N.D. Iowa Aug. 23, 2021).

    Return to citation ^
  85. ^ Complaint for Declaratory and Preliminary and Permanent Injunctive Relief at 1–2, N. Am. Meat Inst. v. Becerra, 420 F. Supp. 3d 1014 (C.D. Cal. 2019) (No. 19-cv-08569).

    Return to citation ^
  86. ^ N. Am. Meat Inst., 420 F. Supp. 3d at 1035.

    Return to citation ^
  87. ^ N. Am. Meat Inst. v. Becerra, No. 19-CV-08569, 2020 WL 919153, at *9 (C.D. Cal. Feb. 24, 2020).

    Return to citation ^
  88. ^ Complaint for Declaratory and Injunctive Relief at 5, Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 456 F. Supp. 3d 1201 (S.D. Cal. 2020) (No. 19-cv-02324).

    Return to citation ^
  89. ^ Nat’l Pork, 456 F. Supp. 3d at 1210.

    Return to citation ^
  90. ^ Nat’l Pork, 6 F.4th at 1025

    Return to citation ^
  91. ^ N. Am. Meat Inst. v. Bonta, 141 S. Ct. 2854, 2854 (2021) (mem.).

    Return to citation ^
  92. ^ Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 142 S. Ct. 1413, 1413 (2022) (mem.).

    Return to citation ^
  93. ^ See, e.g., Holly Honderich & Anthony Zurcher, Key Cases to Watch as US Supreme Court Returns, BBC (Oct. 3, 2022, 7:57 AM), https://www.bbc.com/news/world-us-canada-63122074 [https://perma.cc/3JKS-CXZG] (“The Supreme Court’s decision [in National Pork] will likely have implications for other laws, like those involving climate change and out-of-state travel for abortions, where states impose burdens on others.”).

    Return to citation ^
  94. ^ Wayne D’Angelo, Supreme Court’s Review of California’s Proposition 12 Could Have Implications for State Climate, Energy, and Public Health Legislation, JD Supra (Apr. 6, 2022), https://www.jdsupra.com/legalnews/supreme-court-s-review-of-california-s-7058970 [https://perma.cc/K97H-L25E].

    Return to citation ^
  95. ^ See generally Transcript of Oral Argument, Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (2023) (No. 21-468).

    Return to citation ^
  96. ^ See, e.g., id. at 96–103.

    Return to citation ^
  97. ^ Id. at 96–97.

    Return to citation ^
  98. ^ Id. at 99 (“So what about a law that says you can’t sell fruit in our state if it’s produced — handled by people who are not in the country legally? Is that state law permissible?”).

    Return to citation ^
  99. ^ Id. at 100.

    Return to citation ^
  100. ^ Id. at 101.

    Return to citation ^
  101. ^ Id. at 102–03.

    Return to citation ^
  102. ^ Id. at 95.

    Return to citation ^
  103. ^ Id. at 86, 116.

    Return to citation ^
  104. ^ Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142, 1157 (2023) (“[N]one of this means . . . that any question about the ability of a State to project its power extraterritorially must yield to an ‘almost per se’ rule under the dormant Commerce Clause. This Court has never before claimed so much ‘ground for judicial supremacy under the banner of the dormant Commerce Clause.’” (quoting United Haulers Ass’n v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Mgmt. Auth., 550 U.S. 330, 347 (2007))).

    Return to citation ^
  105. ^ For a thorough description of the National Pork opinion, see generally The Supreme Court, 2022 Term — Leading Cases, 137 Harv. L. Rev. 290, 330–39 (2023).

    Return to citation ^
  106. ^ Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. at 1157 (quoting Gen. Motors Corp. v. Tracy, 519 U.S. 278, 298 n.12 (1997)).

    Return to citation ^
  107. ^ Richard Fallon Jr., The Dynamic Constitution 311 (2d ed. 2013).

    Return to citation ^
  108. ^ Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. at 1159 (opinion of Gorsuch, J.).

    Return to citation ^
  109. ^ Id. (quoting United Haulers, 550 U.S. at 343).

    Return to citation ^
  110. ^ Id. (alteration and omission in original) (quoting Dep’t of Revenue v. Davis, 553 U.S. 328, 353 (2008)).

    Return to citation ^
  111. ^ Id. at 1160–61.

    Return to citation ^
  112. ^ S. 2019, 118th Cong. (2023). The EATS Act would permit individuals to sue to invalidate state laws that “interfer[e] with the production and distribution of agricultural products in interstate commerce.” Id.

    Return to citation ^
  113. ^ Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. at 1161 (opinion of Gorsuch, J.).

    Return to citation ^
  114. ^ Id. at 1166 (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part) (citing id. at 1164–65 (majority opinion)).

    Return to citation ^
  115. ^ Id.

    Return to citation ^
  116. ^ Id. at 1168 (Roberts, C.J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (citing Schneider v. New Jersey, 308 U.S. 147, 162 (1939); Winston v. Lee, 470 U.S. 753, 760 (1985); Addington v. Texas, 441 U.S. 418, 425 (1979)).

    Return to citation ^
  117. ^ See id. at 1168–69 (referencing Schneider, 308 U.S. 147, as an example in the First Amendment context, as well as Winston, 470 U.S. 753, and Addington, 441 U.S. 418, as examples with regard to the Fourth Amendment context). Interestingly, Chief Justice Roberts also alluded to a particular free trade view of the dormant commerce clause, saying that the doctrine “reflects the basic concern . . . that there be ‘free private trade in the national marketplace.’” Id. at 1168 (quoting Gen. Motors Corp. v. Tracy, 519 U.S. 278, 287 (1997)).

    Return to citation ^
  118. ^ Regan, supra note 40, at 1161.

    Return to citation ^
  119. ^ Id. at 1166.

    Return to citation ^
  120. ^ 472 U.S. 38 (1985).

    Return to citation ^
  121. ^ Id. at 50.

    Return to citation ^
  122. ^ 283 U.S. 605 (1931), overruled by Girouard v. United States, 328 U.S. 61 (1946).

    Return to citation ^
  123. ^ Id. at 631–32 (Hughes, C.J., dissenting).

    Return to citation ^
  124. ^ 310 U.S. 296 (1940).

    Return to citation ^
  125. ^ Id. at 303.

    Return to citation ^
  126. ^ 494 U.S. 872 (1990).

    Return to citation ^
  127. ^ Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398, 404 (1963).

    Return to citation ^
  128. ^ Id. at 403–04 (“[T]o withstand . . . challenge, it must be [that] . . . any incidental burden on the free exercise of appellant’s religion may be justified by a ‘compelling state interest in the regulation of a subject within the State’s constitutional power to regulate . . . .’” Id. at 403 (quoting NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. 415, 438 (1963)).).

    Return to citation ^
  129. ^ Pub. L. No. 103-141, 107 Stat. 1488 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 2000bb to 2000bb-4). In City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (1997), RFRA was held unconstitutional as applied to the states, see id. at 536, but the law still applies to federal action, see, e.g., Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S. 682, 690–91 (2014).

    Return to citation ^
  130. ^ 42 U.S.C. § 2000bb(a)(4).

    Return to citation ^
  131. ^ Id. § 2000bb-1.

    Return to citation ^
  132. ^ See Douglas NeJaime & Reva B. Siegel, Conscience Wars: Complicity-Based Conscience Claims in Religion and Politics, 124 Yale L.J. 2516, 2536 n.79 (2015) (“Throughout the 1960s and early 1970s, conscience arguments circulated in debates over war and abortion.”).

    Return to citation ^
  133. ^ By which this Note means “the view that the state should not reward or penalize particular conceptions of the good life but, rather, should provide a neutral framework within which different and potentially conflicting conceptions of the good can be pursued.” Will Kymlicka, Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality, 99 Ethics 883, 883 (1989).

    Return to citation ^
  134. ^ See Daniel F. Piar, Morality as a Legitimate Government Interest, 117 Penn St. L. Rev. 139, 152–56 (2012).

    Return to citation ^
  135. ^ Stephen E. Gottlieb, Morality Imposed: The Rehnquist Court and Liberty in America 62 (2000).

    Return to citation ^
  136. ^ Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Roe Rage: Democratic Constitutionalism and Backlash, 42 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 373, 408 (2007); see also id. at 406–07.

    Return to citation ^
  137. ^ Samuel Enoch Stumpf, The Moral Element in Supreme Court Decisions, 6 Vand. L. Rev. 41, 42 (1952).

    Return to citation ^
  138. ^ E.g., Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S. 682, 724–25 (2014).

    Return to citation ^
  139. ^ Brief for the State Respondents, supra note 81, at 45; see also Brief of Professors Michael Knoll and Ruth Mason as Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioners at 29, Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (2023) (No. 21-468) (“Respondent-intervenors characterize California’s interest as ensuring that Californians buying meat do not become morally complicit in the cruel treatment of animals.”).

    Return to citation ^
  140. ^ Andrew Cornford, Indirect Crimes, 32 Law & Phil. 485, 485 (2013).

    Return to citation ^
  141. ^ Richard B. LeVine, Inc. v. Higashi, 32 Cal. Rptr. 3d 244, 249 (Ct. App. 2005) (quoting 5 B.E. Witkin, Summary of California Law § 44, at 107 (9th ed. 1987)).

    Return to citation ^
  142. ^ Although a state is not directly analogous to a corporation, the Supreme Court has already acknowledged the capacity of a collective entity to have a complicity interest by applying RFRA to closely held corporations. As the Court explained in Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S. 682, “[a] corporation is simply a form of organization used by human beings to achieve desired ends.” Id. at 706.

    Return to citation ^
  143. ^ See Nadine El-Bawab, Everytown Launches Campaign Demanding Colleges, Universities Divest from Gun Industry, ABC News (Jan. 27, 2023, 12:41 PM), https://abcnews.go.com/US/everytown-launches-campaign-demanding-colleges-universities-divest-gun/story?id=96713930 [https://perma.cc/78RP-268Z].

    Return to citation ^
  144. ^ See Steve Ahlquist, Campaign Seeks to Encourage Fossil Fuel Divestment Among RI Municipalities and Non-profits, Uprise RI (Mar. 22, 2023, 4:21 PM), https://upriseri.com/esg-campaign-fossil-fuel-divestment-ri-municipalities-non-profits [https://perma.cc/8ZPY-FZCT].

    Return to citation ^
  145. ^ See Emily Stewart, The Problem with America’s Semi-Rich, Vox (Oct. 12, 2021, 8:00 AM), https://www.vox.com/the-goods/22673605/upper-middle-class-meritocracy-matthew-stewart [https://perma.cc/8P35-UKJP] (“I do think the issue is basically a class that has allowed itself to delude itself about the sources of its own privilege, and its main contribution would be in opening its eyes and then living and working more in accordance with what I think was the original inspiration of the class.”).

    Return to citation ^
  146. ^ “[L]oosely organized” groups may also achieve collective wrongs, so formalized processes and systems are not a necessary feature. See Howard McGary, Morality and Collective Liability, 20 J. Value Inquiry 157, 160 (1986) (discussing collective moral liability of social groups).

    Return to citation ^
  147. ^ See generally Peter A. French, Collective and Corporate Responsibility (1984).

    Return to citation ^
  148. ^ Violetta Igneski, Collective Duties of Beneficence, in The Routledge Handbook of Collective Responsibility 447, 448 (Saba Bazargan-Forward & Deborah Tollefsen eds., 2020) (“[W]hen there is evidence that the group of individuals has the necessary capacity to prevent a harm or wrong and the individuals are aware (or should be aware) of this, they have a duty, as a group, to prevent that harm or wrong.”).

    Return to citation ^
  149. ^ Rachel Kleinfeld & Elena Barham, Complicit States and the Governing Strategy of Privilege Violence: When Weakness Is Not the Problem, 21 Ann. Rev. Pol. Sci. 215, 216 (2018) (emphasis added).

    Return to citation ^
  150. ^ Miles Jackson, Complicity in International Law 3–4 (2015) (offering analytical and normative observations about international rules relating to state complicity).

    Return to citation ^
  151. ^ E.g., Transcript of Oral Argument, supra note 95, at 96–103.

    Return to citation ^
  152. ^ See, e.g., Village of Arlington Heights v. Metro. Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252, 265–68 (1977) (“Determining whether invidious discriminatory purpose was a motivating factor demands a sensitive inquiry into such circumstantial and direct evidence of intent as may be available.” Id. at 266.).

    Return to citation ^
  153. ^ See, e.g., NeJaime & Siegel, supra note 132, at 2522–23 (“The concept of complicity has a richly elaborated theological basis in Catholicism.”); Chiara Lepora & Robert E. Goodin, On Complicity and Compromise 33 (2013); Gregory Mellema, Complicity and Moral Accountability 18–19 (2016).

    Return to citation ^
  154. ^ Lepora & Goodin, supra note 153, at 33.

    Return to citation ^
  155. ^ Id.

    Return to citation ^
  156. ^ Id. at 97.

    Return to citation ^
  157. ^ Lepora and Goodin’s formulation is certainly not the only possibility for assessing whether a valid complicity interest exists.

    Return to citation ^
  158. ^ United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163, 184–85 (1965) (quoting United States v. Ballard, 322 U.S. 78, 86 (1944)).

    Return to citation ^
  159. ^ See id. at 185 (“But we hasten to emphasize that while the ‘truth’ of a belief is not open to question, there remains the significant question whether it is ‘truly held.’ This is the threshold question of sincerity which must be resolved in every case. It is, of course, a question of fact . . . .”).

    Return to citation ^
  160. ^ 336 U.S. 525 (1949).

    Return to citation ^
  161. ^ Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142, 1168 (2023) (Roberts, C.J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (quoting Hood & Sons, 336 U.S. at 539).

    Return to citation ^
  162. ^ Brief of Professors Michael Knoll and Ruth Mason as Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioners, supra note 139, at 18.

    Return to citation ^
  163. ^ Id.

    Return to citation ^
  164. ^ Brief for Petitioners, supra note 5, at 5–6 (quoting Brief of Indiana and Nineteen Other States as Amici Curiae in Support of Petitioners at 13–14, Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (No. 21-468)).

    Return to citation ^
  165. ^ See, e.g., Healy v. Beer Inst., 491 U.S. 324, 326 (1989).

    Return to citation ^
  166. ^ See, e.g., Brief for Petitioners, supra note 5, at 18 (quoting Petition for a Writ of Certiorari app. at 7a, Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. 1142 (No. 21-468)).

    Return to citation ^
  167. ^ “The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people.” U.S. Const. amend. X.

    Return to citation ^
  168. ^ Nat’l Fed’n of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius, 567 U.S. 519, 536 (2012) (“Our cases refer to this general power of governing, possessed by the States but not by the Federal Government, as the ‘police power.’” (citing United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 618–19 (2000))).

    Return to citation ^
  169. ^ Va. Code Ann. § 59.1-576 (2019).

    Return to citation ^
  170. ^ Colo. Rev. Stat. § 6-1-1304 (2023).

    Return to citation ^
  171. ^ Justice Thomas, for example, has called the dormant commerce clause a “failed jurisprudence.” Camps Newfound/Owatonna, Inc. v. Town of Harrison, 520 U.S. 564, 610 (1997) (Thomas, J., dissenting). In Tyler Pipe Industries, Inc. v. Washington State Department of Revenue, 483 U.S. 232 (1987), Justice Scalia called it a “quagmire,” id. at 259 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (quoting Nw. States Portland Cement Co. v. Minnesota, 358 U.S. 450, 458 (1959)), that “ma[kes] no sense,” id. at 260.

    Return to citation ^
  172. ^ See South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 138 S. Ct. 2080, 2091 (2018).

    Return to citation ^
  173. ^ Brief of Professors Michael Knoll and Ruth Mason as Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioners, supra note 139, at 32.

    Return to citation ^
  174. ^ See, e.g., Nat’l Ass’n of Optometrists & Opticians v. Brown, 709 F. Supp. 2d 968, 973–74 (E.D. Cal. 2010) (applying Pike balancing test and upholding health regulations).

    Return to citation ^
  175. ^ See Bibb v. Navajo Freight Lines, Inc., 359 U.S. 520, 529–30 (1959).

    Return to citation ^
  176. ^ Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142, 1174 (2023) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

    Return to citation ^
  177. ^ See Regan, supra note 40, at 1099.

    Return to citation ^
  178. ^ Transcript of Oral Argument, supra note 95, at 102–03.

    Return to citation ^
  179. ^ Cf. South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203, 207 (1987).

    Return to citation ^
  180. ^ See Cal. Health & Safety Code § 25990(b) (West 2010 & Supp. 2023).

    Return to citation ^
  181. ^ Knoll & Mason, supra note 5, at 75.

    Return to citation ^
  182. ^ Id. at 76.

    Return to citation ^
  183. ^ Id. n.350.

    Return to citation ^
  184. ^ U.S. Const. amend. I.

    Return to citation ^
  185. ^ Id. amend. V.

    Return to citation ^
  186. ^ Id. amend. XIV.

    Return to citation ^
  187. ^ NeJaime & Siegel, supra note 132, at 2543.

    Return to citation ^
  188. ^ Id.

    Return to citation ^
  189. ^ Id. at 2559.

    Return to citation ^
  190. ^ See Complaint for Declaratory and Injunctive Relief, supra note 88, at 5.

    Return to citation ^
  191. ^ Id. at 4–5.

    Return to citation ^
  192. ^ Id. at 5.

    Return to citation ^
  193. ^ This decision would admittedly come with significant costs to the producers, but the fact of the matter is that producers are not entitled to the specific type of market that is ideal to their interests. See Nat’l Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 143 S. Ct. 1142, 1162 (2023) (opinion of Gorsuch, J.) (quoting Exxon Corp. v. Governor of Md., 437 U.S. 117, 127 (1978)).

    Return to citation ^
  194. ^ Besides, as the Court previously held in another context, the government cannot artificially create a market for goods that consumers do not want. Nat’l Fed’n of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius, 567 U.S. 519, 558 (2012) (opinion of Roberts, C.J.). This disfavors use of the dormant commerce clause to force creation of a market for goods that California voters have deemed undesirable.

    Return to citation ^
  195. ^ See, e.g., Women’s Health Protection Act of 2023, S. 701, 118th Cong. (2023).

    Return to citation ^
  196. ^ See, e.g., Nat’l Pork, 143 S. Ct. at 1152–53 (quoting, inter alia, Camps Newfound/Owatonna, Inc. v. Town of Harrison, 520 U.S. 564, 581 (1997)) (discussing the antidiscrimination principle in the Court’s Commerce Clause jurisprudence).

    Return to citation ^
  197. ^ See Complaint for Declaratory and Injunctive Relief, supra note 88, at 71.

    Return to citation ^