Animal Law
Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc., ex rel. Happy v. Breheny
New York Court of Appeals Rejects Extending Writ of Habeas Corpus to Elephant.
Elephant is not the new Black.1×1. See generally BĂ©nĂ©dicte Boisseron, Afro-dog: Blackness and the Animal Question (2018) (âIs the Animal the New Black?â Id. at 1.). Happy, a fifty-one-year-old Asian elephant, is a longtime resident of the Bronx Zoo whose solitary confinement spurred legal advocates to petition for a writ of habeas corpus on her behalf.2×2. See Client: Happy (Elephant), Nonhum. Rts. Project, https://www.nonhumanrights.org/client-happy [https://perma.cc/Q5KX-XYHN]. According to the Nonhuman Rights Project (the animal rights organization representing the pachyderm), refusing to recognize Happyâs right to habeas corpus âechoes a long and deeply regrettable history of naked biasesâ3×3. Brief for Petitioner-Appellant at 42, Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc. v. Breheny, No. 52 (N.Y. June 14, 2022).  â notably, the enslavement of African Americans.4×4. See id. Recently, in Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc., ex rel. Happy v. Breheny,5×5. No. 52, 2022 WL 2122141 (N.Y. June 14, 2022). the New York Court of Appeals held that nonhuman animals cannot avail themselves of the writ of habeas corpus because such animals are not persons.6×6. Id. at *1. In rejecting Happyâs petition, the majority rightfully distinguished habeas corpus precedent regarding enslaved persons7×7. This comment utilizes the terminology âenslaved personâ when referring to those people who historically have been called âslaves.â For more information on this diction, see Shannon Browning-Mullis, Why We Use âEnslaved,â Telfair Museums (May 4, 2020), https://www.telfair.org/article/why-we-use-enslaved [https://perma.cc/SGQ9-HRRC] (âThe noun slave implies that she was, at her core, a slave. The adjective enslaved reveals that though in bondage, bondage was not her core existence. Furthermore, she was enslaved by the actions of another.â). from Happyâs case. Reliance on abolition-related precedent to advocate for nonhuman animals is folly under both theories advanced by the appellant;8×8. See Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 13, 20 (arguing either that Happy is person or that writ of habeas corpus has historical flexibility proven by extension to enslaved persons). such analogies are not only fraught with racist implications, but are inapposite to novel extensions of rights to new species as they do not demonstrate the flexibility of legal personhood.
Born in the Asian wilderness, Happy arrived at the Bronx Zoo in 1977.9×9. Happy the Elephant Is Not a Person, A Court Rules, NPR (June 14, 2022, 4:26 PM), https://www.npr.org/2022/06/14/1105031075/bronx-zoo-elephant-not-person-court-rules [https://perma.cc/N9Q3-XT84]. In 2006, Happy passed the mirror test, which demonstrated to âresearchers that pachyderms can recognize themselves in a mirror â complex behavior observed in only a few other species.â10×10. Andrew Bridges, Mirror Test Suggests Elephants Are Self-Aware, NBC News (Oct. 30, 2006, 5:00 PM), https://www.nbcnews.com/id/wbna15487308 [https://perma.cc/NZ8P-DCLM]. Originally, Happy lived gleefully with other elephantine friends, but each of her companions has since passed.11×11. Bill Mahoney, Happy the Elephant at Bronx Zoo Is Not a Person, New Yorkâs Top Court Rules, Politico (June 14, 2022, 10:48 AM), https://www.politico.com/news/2022/06/14/happy-elephant-bronx-zoo-00039409 [https://perma.cc/5VKJ-SUMP]. Woefully, Happy does ânot get alongâ with Patty, the other remaining elephant at the Bronx Zoo, and therefore lives in a solitary enclosure.12×12. Id. Like humans, elephants are communal creatures and âsocial interactions remain central to their well-being throughout their lives.â Rachel Fobar, âNothing to Do, Nowhere to Goâ: What Happens When Elephants Live Alone, Natâl Geographic (Jan. 31, 2022), https://www.nationalgeographic.com/animals/article/what-happens-when-captive-us-elephants-live-alone [https://perma.cc/A3DW-3DE3].
In 2018, the Nonhuman Rights Project (NhRP) commenced a habeas corpus proceeding against James Breheny, the director of the Bronx Zoo, on behalf of Happy.13×13. Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc. v. Breheny, No. 260441/19, 2020 WL 1670735, at *2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Feb. 18, 2020). NhRP alleged that Happy âis being unlawfully imprisoned,â is âdenied direct social contact with any other elephants, and spends most of her time indoors.â14×14. Id. The Supreme Court of New York dismissed the petition, stating that âanimals are not âpersonsâ entitled to rights and protections afforded by the writ of habeas corpus.â15×15. Id. at *9 (citing Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., ex rel. Tommy v. Lavery, 100 N.E.3d 846 (N.Y. 2018) (Fahey, J., concurring)).
In a brief opinion, the New York Appellate Division affirmed the Supreme Courtâs conclusion, stating that âthe writ of habeas corpus is limited to human beings.â16×16. Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., ex rel. Happy v. Breheny, 134 N.Y.S.3d 188, 189 (App. Div. 2020) (mem.) (citing Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., ex rel. Tommy v. Lavery, 54 N.Y.S.3d 392, 393â95 (App. Div. 2017)). Undeterred, NhRP appealed the lower courtsâ determination to the highest court of New York.17×17. See Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., 2022 WL 2122141, at *1.
The New York Court of Appeals affirmed the decisions of the lower courts.18×18. Id. Writing for the majority, Chief Judge DiFiore19×19. Chief Judge DiFiore was joined by Judges Garcia, Singas, Cannataro, and Troutman. Id. at *43. concluded that the Supreme Courtâs dismissal of Happyâs habeas corpus claim was proper as the common law writ has only been used to release âhuman beingsâ from âunlawful confinement.â20×20. Id. at *1. To generate this conclusion, the majority first considered the lack of judicial precedent supporting âthe notion that the writ . . . should be applicable to nonhuman animals.â21×21. Id. at *4. New York statutes do not confer personhood on any nonhuman animals and declare that all wildlife not privately owned is property of the State.22×22. Id. Although âthe writ of habeas corpus is flexibleâ and has been used to secure liberty for âthose whose rights had not yet been properly acknowledged through established law,â Chief Judge DiFiore declined to extend the breadth of the writâs precedent to encompass nonhuman animals.23×23. Id. Despite the numerous biological experts and cognitive scientific evidence introduced by the appellant, the majority relied on a definition of legal personhood that describes persons as those âconnected with the capacity, not just to benefit from the provision of legal rights, but also to assume legal duties and social responsibilities.â24×24. Id. This definition was consonant with the personhood of corporate and partnership entities because â[c]orporations are simply legal constructs through which human beings act and corporate entities, unlike nonhuman animals, bear legal duties in exchange for legal rights.â Id. at *5 (citing Pembina Consol. Silver Mining & Milling Co. v. Pennsylvania, 125 U.S. 181, 189 (1888)).
Finally, the majority stated that the extension of nonhuman personhood should be left to the legislature, as a contrary decision would create an âinevitable floodâ of litigation against âfarmers, pet owners, military and police forces, researchers, and zoos.â25×25. Id. Before concluding, the majority attempted to dispel any notion that the courtâs holding would further cruel treatment of nonhuman animals by emphasizing that New York law already requires humans to âtreat nonhuman animals with dignity and respect.â26×26. Id. at *7.
The heart of Judge Wilsonâs dissent was the Latin maxim â[t]empora mutantur et leges mutantur in illis,â that is, that â[t]imes change and the laws change with them.â27×27. Id. at *12 (Wilson, J., dissenting). Judge Wilson began by describing the unfortunate life of Ota Benga, âa member of the Mbuti people,â who had been put on âdisplay in the [Bronx] Zooâs monkey house[] behind iron barsâ in 1906.28×28. Id. at *7. Judge Wilson made much of the similarities between Mr. Bengaâs and Happyâs respective imprisonments at the Bronx Zoo; notably that both confinements, âthough not in violation of any statutory law, produced little or no social benefit.â29×29. Id. at *8. He redefined the legal question identified by the majority, asserting that this case was not about Happyâs personhood, but rather âwhether the detention of an elephant can ever be so cruel, so antithetical to the essence of an elephant, that the writ of habeas corpus should be made available under the common law.â30×30. Id. In his view, this case presented a novel issue for the court to resolve, and the majorityâs reliance on the historical use of habeas corpus was âan argument against all progress, one that flies in the face of legal history.â31×31. Id. at *11.
Judge Wilson next chronicled precedent of the writ of habeas corpusâs application to enslaved persons.32×32. See id. at *14â17. Although âthe various rights held by animals today . . . are far greater than those held by enslaved persons,â the writ of habeas corpus was still available to the latter.33×33. Id. at *14. These stories proved that the writ of habeas corpus could be invoked to challenge legal confinements on behalf of chattel and persons with negligible rights and no legal existence, even when such applications were unconventional.34×34. Id. at *22. Judge Wilson then detailed the difficulties that arise when using the stories of enslaved and subjugated persons to advocate for animal rights.35×35. Id. at *26.
Judge Rivera also dissented,36×36. Id. at *34 (Rivera, J., dissenting). arguing that âif humans without full rights and responsibilities under the law may invoke the writ to challenge an unjust denial of freedom, so too may any other autonomous being, regardless of species.â37×37. Id. at *36. Judge Rivera underscored that the majorityâs opinion was âglaringly absent [of] any explanation of why some kinds of animals â i.e., humans â may seek habeas relief, while others â e.g., elephants â may not.â38×38. Id. at *38. Embracing the equitable nature of habeas corpus proceedings, Judge Rivera deduced that such questions fall within the purview of the courts as the âdifficultly [sic] of the task . . . is no basis to shrink from our judicial obligation.â39×39. Id. Judge Rivera concluded her dissent with the proclamation that Happyâs captivity is âan affront to a civilized society, and every day she remains a captive â a spectacle for humans â we, too, are diminished.â40×40. Id. at *43.
Ultimately, the utilization of precedent involving enslaved persons likely contributed to NhRPâs loss. For Happy to avail herself of the writ of habeas corpus, the appellant needed to demonstrate either that Happy is a person (the âpersonhoodâ argument) or that the writ is applicable to nonpersons (the âflexibilityâ argument).41×41. The majority and dissents fractured on the legal issue at hand. To meet this burden, NhRP analogized to precedent involving enslaved persons, a familiar technique of animal advocacy. However, under both theories, analogies between Black people and animals cannot be uncoupled from racism because the user intends to equate the horrors of enslavement with the horrors of animal captivity; or operate within, and validate, the legal frameworks constructed by enslavers. Even if an advocate wishes to assert that nonhuman animals are equal to all humans, the targeted use of precedent involving enslaved persons still encourages racial harm without furthering this equitable goal.
A lawyerâs sword is the analogy;42×42. See Cass R. Sunstein, On Analogical Reasoning, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 741, 741 (1993) (âReasoning by analogy is the most familiar form of legal reasoning.â). the distinction, their shield. When a lawyer cites precedent, they are asserting that there is something to be learned from the reference.43×43. See Precedent, Blackâs Law Dictionary (4th ed. 1968). When utilizing an analogy, the lawyer argues that the similarities between two cases call for a judge to recreate the result of the earlier case.44×44. See Sunstein, supra note 42, at 745. Indeed, the appellant quoted Enright v. Eli Lilly & Co.45×45. 570 N.E.2d 198 (N.Y. 1991). for the proposition that â[i]t is âa fundamental principle of justiceâ under the common law that âlike cases should be treated alike.ââ46×46. See Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 37 (quoting Enright, 570 N.E.2d at 204).
NhRP asserted that refusing to recognize Happyâs right to habeas corpus âechoes a long and deeply regrettable history of naked biases.â47×47. Id. at 42. The appellant pointed to Dred Scott v. Sanford,48×48. 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393 (1857) (enslaved party), superseded by constitutional amendment, U.S. Const. amend. XIV. which stated that Black people âhad no rights which the white man was bound to respect.â49×49. Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 42 (quoting Dred Scott, 60 U.S. (19 How.) at 407). NhRP also offered Somerset v. Stewart,50×50. (1772) 98 Eng. Rep. 499; 12 Geo. 3 (KB) (enslaved person at issue). a British case âsuccessfully brought by [a] slave,â which was relied upon by the New York Court of Appeals in Lemmon v. People51×51. 20 N.Y. 562 (1860). to free enslaved persons through the writ of habeas corpus.52×52. Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 14. For these analogies to be of any use, the appellant must allege that there exists some material similarity between the enslaved persons described in Somerset and Lemmon, and Happy; otherwise, these citations would represent nothing more than historical fluff.53×53. It is improbable that the similarities are alleged to be merely between Happyâs confinement and the confinement of these enslaved persons; if that were the case, then the appellant could have relied solely on cases that did not involve enslaved individuals. The appellantâs brief sets out to prove the equitable nature of the writ of habeas corpus54×54. See Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 13â17. (the âflexibilityâ argument) and that persons can âhave only one or any number of rightsâ55×55. See id. at 20. (the âpersonhoodâ argument). The dissents relied solely on the flexibility argument.56×56. See Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., 2022 WL 2122141, at *20 (Wilson, J., dissenting); id. at *34 (Rivera, J., dissenting).
If the appellant sought to compare the dehumanization of enslaved Africans to Happyâs nonpersonhood, it created an âodious comparison with concerning implications.â57×57. See id. at *4 (majority opinion). As Professor BĂ©nĂ©dicte Boisseron notes, â[t]he black-animal subtext is deeply ingrained in the cultural genet-ics of the global north, an inherited condition informed by a shared history of slavery and colonization.â58×58. Boisseron, supra note 1, at ix. Regrettably, animal advocates from Jeremy Bentham to the People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA) have contributed to this legion of âodious comparisons.â59×59. For example, in 1789, Jeremy Bentham âfamously drew attention to the connection that one should make between the movement to end slavery and the need to extend moral considerations to animals.â Id. at 4 (citing Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (London, W. Pickering & E. Wilson 1823) (1789)). In 1988, Marjorie Spiegel published The Dreaded Comparison: Human and Animal Slavery, a book that compares the horrors faced by enslaved people to the horrors of animal cruelty. See Marjorie Spiegel, The Dreaded Comparison: Human and Animal Slavery 14, 17 (1988). In 2020, PETA compared âspeciesismâ to âracismâ in a âColin Kaepernickâinspired adâ that was allegedly banned by the National Football League. See Banned! NFL Blocks PETAâs Award-Winning Super Bowl Commercial, PETA, https://headlines.peta.org/super-bowl-end-speciesism [https://perma.cc/G849-MSMH]. At their best, these invocations of race co-opt the Black struggle in order to advocate for another, unrelated cause.60×60. See Katherine Compitus, What Does the BLM Movement Have to Do with Animal Rights?, Psych. Today (Aug. 31, 2020), https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/zooeyia/202008/what-does-the-blm-movement-have-do-animal-rights [https://perma.cc/5QNC-9LQ5] (interviewing Boisseron who states that â[i]n more general terms, the problem with this type of comparison is that it instrumentalizes one cause for the benefit of another, without much regard for the former causeâ); cf. Jay Shooster, Note, Justice for All: Including Animal Rights in Social Justice Activism, 40 The Harbinger 39, 41 (2015) (âJust like racism, sexism, and classism, speciesism focuses on one morally arbitrary characteristic: species, and uses that to justify violence and inequality.â). At their worst, these appropriations suggest that the differences between white people and Black people parallel the differences between humans and nonhuman animals.61×61. See, e.g., Adrian Brune, PETA Exhibit Provokes Anger from Blacks, Orlando Sentinel, (Oct. 5, 2005, 12:00 AM), https://www.orlandosentinel.com/news/os-xpm-2005-10-05-peta05-1-story.html [https://perma.cc/B4LN-HBUA] (describing public reaction to PETA exhibit featuring âphotograph of a lynching of a black man in Indiana offset by an Angus cow hanging by its feet at a slaughterhouseâ and âan African-Americanâs chained foot opposite the equally shackled limb of a circus elephant,â among other provocative pieces). Judge Wilson, who is Black, see Glenn Blain & Kenneth Lovett, Senate Approves Gov. Cuomoâs Pick for Court of Appeals, N.Y. Daily News (Feb. 6, 2017, 6:03 PM), https://www.nydailynews.com/news/politics/senate-approves-gov-cuomo-pick-court-appeals-article-1.2965743 [https://perma.cc/RZ85-ZNRJ] (stating that Judge Wilson would be âthe second current member of the seven-member court who is blackâ), attempted to assuage the fear of false equivalency between Black people and nonhuman animals by including a discussion of the racist implications historically used by animal rights advocates to obtain nonhuman animal justice. See Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., 2022 WL 2122141, at *26â27 (Wilson, J., dissenting).
Denials of personhood based on species cannot be conflated with denials of personhood based on race. As Professor Ian Haney LĂłpez observes, âraces do not have a biological basis,â62×62. Ian F. Haney LĂłpez, The Social Construction of Race: Some Observations on Illusion, Fabrication, and Choice, 29 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 1, 11 (1994). and instead must be understood as mere âsocial construction[s].â63×63. Id. at 27. Thus, extending the writ of habeas corpus to enslaved persons is not revolutionary; it is instead demonstrative of basic empathy â the belated recognition that another human being is a person for the exact same reason as any other human. The personhood of enslaved Blacks was merely obscured and minimized by the racist and sexist attitudes of predominantly white, cisgender male legislatures.64×64. See Henry L. Chambers, Jr., Dred Scott: Tiered Citizenship and Tiered Personhood, 82 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 209, 212â13 (2007). Contrarily, the determination of species is almost entirely a biological endeavor.65×65. See, e.g., James MacDonald, What Makes a Species?, JSTOR Daily (Sept. 21, 2016), https://daily.jstor.org/what-makes-a-species [https://perma.cc/2KLE-UPNW]. It should be noted that determination of species is frequently a tricky endeavor, as the traditional reproduction-based methods of determining distinct species are not always accurate. See Species, Natâl Geographic, https://education.nationalgeographic.org/resource/species [https://perma.cc/2U3G-6ZYE]. Therefore, when asking if a nonhuman animal species is a person, the determination is about more than empathy â it entails determining whether the species has a similar capacity for sentience as human beings.66×66. This point is proven by the fact that NhRP introduced mountains of expert evidence regarding Happyâs intelligence and capability for autonomy. See Nonhum. Rts. Project, Inc., 2022 WL 2122141, at *2. The use of precedent involving enslaved humans does not provide support for this determination.
Even within the âflexibilityâ argument, appeals to precedent involving enslaved African Americans still further racial harm. The âflexibilityâ argument only falls in Happyâs favor if one assumes that there is something materially different between enslaved African Americans and white men. If enslaved African Americans and white men are identical, then the writ of habeas corpus is as flexible as a board. As NhRP and the dissenting judges demonstrate, it can be tempting to identify differences between enslaved African Americans and white men and articulate them as merely âlegal.â However, to utilize such an argument is to operate within the moral and ethical frame constructed by enslavers. That is, when discussing the personhood of human beings and divorcing legal personhood from true personhood, one assumes that there is some tangible, logical (perhaps, microscopic) basis for this distinction other than pure racism.67×67. One such justification could be the presumed validity of statutes passed by democratic legislatures in societies with limited suffrage. But enslaved people are persons for the same reason that adult, white cisgender men are persons: we belong to a species with the same capacity for thought, love, and responsibility.68×68. For a brief examination of the ways that science has been used to entrench and justify racial hierarchies, see generally William H. Tucker, The Ideology of Racism: Misusing Science to Justify Racial Discrimination, United Nations Chron., https://www.un.org/en/chronicle/article/ideology-racism-misusing-science-justify-racial-discrimination [https://perma.cc/2FH9-HUVW]. In contrast, Happy the Elephant is an elephant.69×69. Bridges, supra note 10. Even under the most flexible personhood standard, it is likely that some species of nonhuman animals would fail.70×70. See, e.g., Melissa Gaskill, No Brain? For Jellyfish, No Problem, PBS: Nature (Nov. 20, 2018), https://www.pbs.org/wnet/nature/blog/no-brain-for-jellyfish-no-problem [https://perma.cc/J2H7-FYZW].
A little over one hundred years ago, Ota Benga looked through the iron bars that confined him, and saw faces just like his own â whiter skin, of course â but each with two eyes, a mouth, and a nose configured in much the same manner as almost every other human in the world.71×71. See generally Pamela Newkirk, Caged Congolese Teen: Why a Zoo Took 114 Years to Apologize, BBC (Aug. 27, 2020), https://www.bbc.com/news/world-africa-53917733 [https://perma.cc/PJY5-YNA9]. When those white masks contorted into giggles, stretched into gasps, and exploded into wonder, perhaps he recognized those sensations as things he himself had experienced in Congo before he was imprisoned like a monkey in a zoo.72×72. See id. Even as he was overwhelmed by his own dread, Ota Benga could still contemplate the sensations of joy within the mind of each onlooker. Maybe this understanding led to the despair which drove him to take his own life.73×73. See id.
Targeted reliance on the struggles of Black people to advocate for nonhuman animals is an offense to the legacies of those who were enslaved or imprisoned. As Professor Justin Simard states, ârelying on a case based in human bondage proves more complicated than a narrow focus on the holding would suggest.â74×74. Justin Simard, Citing Slavery, 72 Stan. L. Rev. 79, 99 (2020). Hence, when referencing a case in which a Black personâs subpersonhood is material to the legal conclusion, one is faced with an unspoken choice: to either (a) accept the logic of the case or (b) throw it all out. The appellant (and, to a lesser degree, the dissents) elected for the former.75×75. As NhRPâs brief stated: â[I]n the early nineteenth century Black slaves in New York only had statutory rights to a jury trial, to own and transfer property by will, to marry, and to bear legitimate children. They were not âpersonsâ in âthe whole senseâ because they lacked every other right.â Brief for Petitioner-Appellant, supra note 3, at 20 (footnote omitted) (quoting Byrn v. N.Y.C. Health & Hosps. Corp., 286 N.E.2d 887, 888 (N.Y. 1972)) (citing Edgar J. McManus, A History of Negro Slavery in New York 63, 65, 177â78 (1st ed. 1966)). This observation, when utilized for the purposes of justifying the extension of some rights to a nonhuman animal, validates the assumption that some persons can be and have been âmoreâ of a person than others. While Happy the Elephant still suffers in solitude, perhaps Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Breheny portends the deserved demise of offensive, ineffective analogies to abolition precedent in the realm of animal advocacy.
Â