Freedom of Speech
Wollschlaeger v. Governor of Florida
Eleventh Circuit Upholds Florida Law Banning Doctors from Inquiring About Patients' Gun Ownership When Such Inquiry Is Irrelevant to Medical Care.
Over the past two years, courts have begun to address a vital question at the heart of the First Amendment: what level of scrutiny should apply when states restrict a doctorâs speech to a patient? In Pickup v. Brown,1×1. 728 F.3d 1042 (9th Cir. 2013), amended on denial of rehâg, 740 F.3d 1208 (9th Cir. 2014). the Ninth Circuit upheld a ban on sexual orientation conversion therapy (SOCT) as applied to minors, exempting from First Amendment protection all medical speech classifiable as treatment.2×2. See id. at 1048, 1056; Pickup, 740 F.3d at 1222, 1231. One year later, in King v. Governor of New Jersey,3×3. No. 13-4429, 2014 WL 4455009 (3d Cir. Sept. 11, 2014). the Third Circuit upheld a parallel ban, this time applying intermediate First Amendment scrutiny.4×4. Id. at *13, *24. A regulation survives intermediate scrutiny only if it ââdirectly advancesâ [a] âsubstantialâ government interest and is ânot more extensive than is necessary to serve that interest.ââ Id. at *13 (quoting Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv. Commân, 447 U.S. 557, 566 (1980)). Last year, in Wollschlaeger v. Governor of Florida,5×5. 760 F.3d 1195 (11th Cir. 2014). the Eleventh Circuit provided its answer. Upholding a Florida law banning doctors from questioning patients about firearm ownership, the court held that because the ban restricts only speech uttered by a doctor in the examination room, it is exempt from First Amendment scrutiny.6×6. See id. at 1225. In June, the Supreme Court denied certiorari in Pickup,7×7. Pickup v. Brown, 134 S. Ct. 2871 (2014) (mem.). leaving it to the circuits, for now, to develop a doctrinal answer to this emerging question. It is thus critical that other circuits recognize the problems at the heart of the Eleventh Circuitâs approach: Wollschlaeger not only removes First Amendment protection from an unprecedented amount of speech, but does so on the basis of a problematic normative premise â that doctors have no âgeneralized interest in being able to speak freelyâ to their patients within the context of the doctor-patient relationship on subjects irrelevant to medical care.8×8. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1215. If allowed to flourish, this premise could lead not only to the vast expansion of government power over professional speech, but to a fundamental alteration of American citizenship.
In 2011, Florida passed the Firearm Ownersâ Privacy Act,9×9. Act of June 2, 2011, 2011 Fla. Laws 1176 (codified at Fla. Stat. §§ 381.026, 456.072, 790.338 (2014)). subjecting doctors to disciplinary measures for, inter alia, making a âverbal or written inquiryâ into patientsâ firearm ownership when doctors do not âin good faith believe[]â such inquiries to be ârelevant to the patientâs medical care or safety, or the safety of others.â10×10. Fla Stat. § 790.338(2); see id. § 456.072(nn). The Act also bans physicians from entering information on gun ownership into a patientâs medical records if they âknow[]â such information is similarly irrelevant, id. § 790.338(1), from discriminating against patients on the basis of firearm ownership, id. § 790.338(5), and from âunnecessarily harassingâ patients about the same, id. § 790.338(6). Citizens and legislators had complained that doctors were repeatedly asking about gun ownership, orally and in questionnaires,11×11. One legislator suggested such questions constituted âa political . . . attack on the constitutional right to own a . . . firearm.â Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1232 (Wilson, J., dissenting) (omissions in original) (internal quotation marks omitted). in part as a result of the American Medical Associationâs suggestion in its policy guides that such questions were important to child safety and public health.12×12. See id. at 1230, 1232â33. Some Floridians further claimed that their doctors had terminated service when they refused to answer such questions. Id. at 1204 n.2 (majority opinion). Though the Act bans discrimination, however, it âdoes not alter existing law regarding a physicianâs authorization to choose his or her patients.â Fla. Stat. § 790.338(4).
Four days after Governor Rick Scott signed the Act into law, a group of medical professionals filed suit, alleging that the Act facially violated the First and Fourteenth Amendments as a content-based, overbroad, and unconstitutionally vague restriction on speech.13×13. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1205. The district court agreed and enjoined enforcement of the law,14×14. See Wollschlaeger v. Farmer, 880 F. Supp. 2d 1251, 1270 (S.D. Fla. 2012). After establishing that the plaintiffs had standing, id. at 1259, the district court found the Act an impermissible content-based regulation of physiciansâ speech, id. at 1267, and found the relevancy requirement inscrutably vague, id. at 1268. and the State appealed, arguing that the Act was a permissible regulation of professional conduct, not speech, and thus exempt from First Amendment scrutiny.15×15. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1207. The State also argued that the Act should survive First Amendment scrutiny as a regulation narrowly tailored to the governmentâs interests, which included âpatient privacy, protecting Second Amendment rights, preventing barriers for firearm owners to receive medical care, and preventing harassment and discrimination of firearm-owning patients.â Id. The State also renewed its argument that the plaintiffs lacked standing. See id.
The Eleventh Circuit reversed. Judge Tjoflat,16×16. Judge Tjoflat was joined by Judge Coogler, sitting by designation from the United States District Court for the Northern District of Alabama. writing for a two-judge majority, upheld the Act as a permissible regulation of professional conduct with only incidental effects on speech. After finding that the plaintiffs had standing,17×17. See Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1208â13. the majority synthesized the Stateâs concerns into an interest in protecting patientsâ privacy.18×18. See id. at 1213â17. Given this interest and the power imbalance inherent in the doctor-patient relationship,19×19. See id. at 1214â15. The court found that, because a patient must rely on a doctorâs expertise and discretion, and because some rural areas might have only one doctor, a doctor occupies a special position from which unwanted questions might reasonably be perceived as coercive. See id. the court found that the Act âmerely reaffirmsâ the âcommon-sense propositionâ that âthe practice of good medicine should not require inquiry into private mattersâ irrelevant to medical care.20×20. Id. at 1215. The court then extended this logic beyond inquiry to all speech: âInsofar as [doctors] claim a generalized interest in being able to speak freely to their patients, such conversation (if not relevant to medical care) is outside the boundaries of the physician-patient relationship.â21×21. Id.
Having described the Act as a presumptively reasonable regulation of conduct, the court then found that the Act does not impermissibly restrict protected speech. The court began by explaining that the Actâs restrictions on a doctorâs ability to engage in âunrestricted debateâ on matters of âpublic concernâ22×22. Id. at 1221. The court conceded that debate on firearms might indeed be a âmatter of public concernâ as that concept was understood in Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207 (2011). See Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1221. solely affect speech uttered âwithin the confines of the physicianâs examination room, where the physician exercises his or her judgment to deliver professional treatment and advice to a particular patient . . . in private.â23×23. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1219. Because the First Amendment concerns implicated by professional speech in this context âapproach a nadir,â24×24. Id. at 1218. the Actâs impact on protected speech is merely incidental25×25. Id. at 1225. As precedent, the court cited Justice Whiteâs concurrence in Lowe v. SEC, 472 U.S. 181 (1985), which suggested that the state could regulate speech incidental to the âpractice of a professionâ with no First Amendment barrier provided that a âpersonal nexus between professional and clientâ could be found, id. at 211 (White, J., concurring in the result) (upholding a restriction on what advice unlicensed investment advisers could offer clients). See Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1218. Such a nexus would be âat its most significantâ within an examination room. Id. at 1219. Similarly, in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992), the Supreme Court found âno constitutional infirmity,â id. at 884 (opinion of OâConnor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.), when a requirement that doctors inform patients about the risks of abortion âimplicated [physiciansâ speech rights], but only as part of the practice of medicine,â id. (citation omitted). The majority then addressed the argument that Lowe merely permitted licensing regimes regulating entry into a profession to evade First Amendment scrutiny, and thus could not be used to justify direct regulations of professional speech. See Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1221â25. The court pointed to two cases, Casey and Pickup, in which other courts had upheld internal regulations of doctorsâ speech. Though there was ambiguity as to whether Casey had exempted its regulation from First Amendment scrutiny altogether, Casey nevertheless demonstrated that a regulation of medical speech could reach beyond the licensing stage, see id. at 1222â23, and though Pickupâs exemption was limited, the treatment/speech line was hardly clear: an inquiry into firearm ownership could be the âopening salvo in an attempt to treatâ medical issues related to firearms, id. at 1224. : it âimplicates physiciansâ speech only âas part of the practice of medicine.ââ26×26. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1220 (quoting Casey, 505 U.S. at 884 (opinion of OâConnor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.)). The court thus conducted no content- or viewpoint-neutrality inquiry27×27. The majority did not expressly articulate the level of scrutiny it applied, but the dissent described it as ârational-basis review.â Id. at 1249 (Wilson, J., dissenting). and upheld Floridaâs ban.28×28. The majority also rejected the plaintiffsâ vagueness challenge. See id. at 1226â30 (majority opinion). The plaintiffs argued that it was unclear what sort of inquiry would be ârelevantâ to medical care, in particular because physicians had a general belief â which they considered to be held in good faith â that all such inquiries were relevant, yet such an interpretation would render the Act meaningless. See id. at 1227. Judge Tjoflat held that an ad hoc showing of relevance, âbased on the specifics of [each] patientâs case,â id. at 1228, would be required: the doctorsâ general belief that such inquiries were relevant would not suffice under the Act. See id. He further held that the Act was not vague in its treatment of relevance, as it clearly applied to âphysicians who wish to pursue an agenda unrelated to medical care or safety.â Id. at 1229.
Judge Wilson filed a vehement dissent. The majority had upheld not only a clear restriction of speech, rather than a mere regulation of professional conduct, but also a content-, speaker-,29×29. See id. at 1236 (Wilson, J., dissenting) (âThe Act proscribes speech about one topic (firearms) by one group of speakers (medical professionals).â). and viewpoint-discriminatory30×30. See id. at 1239 (â[T]he legislative history confirms that the purpose of the Act was to silence firearm-safety messages . . . perceived as âpolitical attacksâ and as part of a âpolitical agendaâ . . . .â). one: Floridaâs ban silenced doctors on a single topic to prevent them from communicating an unpopular message to Floridaâs citizenry.31×31. See id. at 1231 (âThe poor fit between what the Act actually does and the interests it purportedly serves belies Floridaâs true purpose in passing [it]: silencing doctorsâ disfavored message about firearm safety. This, the State cannot do.â). More dangerously, the majority reached this result not after subjecting the Act to First Amendment scrutiny, but by issuing a new rule, unsupported by precedent,32×32. The dissent argued that the Supreme Court had âconsistently subject[ed] content-, speaker-, and viewpoint-based restrictions to at least intermediate . . . scrutiny,â id. at 1236, and had tolerated carve-outs in this fabric of protection only based on historical evidence of proscription â evidence lacking in the context of physiciansâ speech, id. at 1236â37 (citing United States v. Alvarez, 132 S. Ct. 2537, 2544 (2012) (plurality opinion)). Further, the majorityâs suggestions notwithstanding, no case had ever previously permitted direct regulation of medical speech without First Amendment scrutiny. See id. at 1239â48. Lowe merely permitted the state to regulate speech âas a consequence of a professional licensing scheme,â id. at 1241, and only when the regulation was content neutral, see id. at 1239â41, and Casey stated that âFirst Amendment rights . . . [were] implicatedâ by the challenged regulation therein, id. at 1245 (omission in original) (quoting Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 884 (1992) (opinion of OâConnor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.)) (internal quotation marks omitted). Pickup, too, was inapposite: Pickup exempted from scrutiny only speech classifiable as treatment, and speech could not possibly be both irrelevant to medical care and itself medical treatment. See id. at 1247â48. that all speech within âthe confines of a one-on-one professional relationshipâ between doctors and patients was, and would now be, exempted from First Amendment scrutiny.33×33. Id. at 1237. The majority, addressing the dissentâs fears, had noted emphatically that it was not creating a rule âwhereby any law burdening speech â such as a law barring doctors from discussing the Affordable Care Act . . . will avoid First Amendment scrutiny so long as the law applies within the confines of a one-on-one professional relationship.â Id. at 1225 n.17 (majority opinion). The dissent, however, found nothing in the majorityâs reasoning or rhetoric to support this disclaimer: âUnder the Majorityâs new exception,â â[s]tates are left free to eliminate all irrelevant speech from a doctorâs office, all relevant speech from a doctorâs office, or just that speech which conflicts with the Stateâs preferred viewpoints.â Id. at 1237 (Wilson, J., dissenting). Rejecting this withdrawal of protection, the dissent would have invalidated the law under either intermediate or strict scrutiny.34×34. Id. at 1237 (Wilson, J., dissenting). The dissent did not decide which level of scrutiny would apply. See id. Instead, Judge Wilson acknowledged that a regulation of speech might be justified by many of the Stateâs claimed interests, see id. at 1231, but determined Florida had produced at best anecdotal evidence that doctorsâ speech had contributed to any of these harms, see id. at 1256â58. Even intermediate scrutiny required more than a mere anecdotal showing. Id. at 1265. The dissent also addressed the plaintiffsâ vagueness challenge. See id. at 1267â70. The dissent suggested that the Actâs âgood faithâ language could be read, on its face, to permit doctors to make inquiries âas a matter of course,â yet the âlegislative historyâ suggested it was precisely these inquiries the Act sought to ban, as the majority itself held. Id. at 1268; see also id. at 1228 (majority opinion). Thus, doctors would be left completely uncertain when a belief in medical relevance would be in âgood faith,â resulting in a chilling effect that would prevent them from conveying âpotentially lifesaving medical information.â Id. at 1231 (Wilson, J., dissenting).
Wollschlaeger serves as the Eleventh Circuitâs contribution to an emerging judicial inquiry: what degree of First Amendment scrutiny should apply when a state restricts a doctorâs speech to a patient? Exempting virtually all speech uttered in the examination room from First Amendment scrutiny, in part on the basis of the normative premise that doctors have no expressive interest in speaking to patients on subjects irrelevant to medical care, Wollschlaeger should be understood as a deeply problematic contribution to this emerging body of opinions. If followed, it would do more than simply permit the state to regulate a vast amount of speech with no meaningful judicial check: it would fundamentally alter a doctorâs status as a professional citizen.
Nearly two years ago, in Pickup, the Ninth Circuit considered to what degree a doctorâs speech to a patient is protected by the First Amendment. Faced with a ban on the application of SOCT to minors, a ban supported by Californiaâs interest in âprotecting the well-beingâ of those minors,35×35. Pickup v. Brown, 740 F.3d 1208, 1231 (9th Cir. 2014). but nevertheless directly regulating a doctorâs speech, the court created a First Amendment bifurcation: speech that could be classified as medical treatment would receive no First Amendment protection, permitting the state wide latitude to regulate dangerous or ineffective therapies,36×36. See id. at 1229â30. but speech merely related to medical care or unrelated altogether would retain intermediate First Amendment protection.37×37. The court emphasized that California did not â[p]revent mental health providers from expressing their views to patients, whether children or adults, about [SOCT], homosexuality, or any other topic,â id. at 1223, and that a regulation of such speech, unlike the present regulation, would receive intermediate scrutiny: â[W]ithin the confines of a professional relationship, First Amendment protection of a professionalâs speech is somewhat diminished,â id. at 1228. Dissenting from a denial of rehearing en banc, Judge OâScannlain, reserving judgment on the merits, lambasted the construction of this exemption.38×38. Id. at 1216 (OâScannlain, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc) (arguing that the court had handed the State âa new and powerful tool to silence expression based on a political or moral judgment about the content and purpose of the communicationsâ). Nevertheless, the courtâs decision constituted a sincere attempt to balance the Stateâs needs against a doctorâs rights: in applying intermediate scrutiny to much of a doctorâs speech, the court implicitly recognized that doctors have some right to speak freely to their patients on subjects of political or moral concern.
One year later, the majority in Wollschlaeger eviscerated this balance.39×39. See Jennifer Keighley, Physician Conduct? Or Speech? Or Both?, Balkinization (Oct. 15, 2014, 8:30 AM), http://balkin.blogspot.com/#3639781212226886059 [http://perma.cc/4XC-D3PP]. Approaching the question of how much First Amendment protection to afford to medical speech, the court eschewed Pickupâs treatment/speech dichotomy in favor of a blanket context-based withdrawal of protection: if a regulation restricts only speech uttered âwithin the confines of the physicianâs examination room,â40×40. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1219. its âburden . . . on speech is . . . incidental to its legitimate regulation of the practice of medicine.â41×41. Id. at 1225. In other words, in the Eleventh Circuit, the First Amendment now ends at the examination room door.42×42. The majority stressed that âphysicians . . . remain largely free . . . to discuss firearm safetyâ with patients, id. at 1224, yet, insofar as this statement is true, it does not alter the decisionâs breadth. Wollschlaegerâs rule would remove protection from this speech as surely as it removed protection from the speech actually banned. See id. at 1253 (Wilson, J., dissenting). A courtâs deference to the legislature is not rendered less deferential because the government stays its hand.
Of course, the Wollschlaeger court disclaimed this broad reading of its rule.43×43. See id. at 1225 n.17 (majority opinion). Invoking the limitation of Floridaâs ban to medically irrelevant speech,44×44. See id. at 1215. the majority suggested its holding might similarly be limited â or at least reasonable â because it did no more than recognize the âcommon-senseâ normative âpropositionâ that doctors have no âgeneralized interest in being able to speak freely to their patients . . . [on subjects] not relevant to medical care.â45×45. Id.; see also id. at 1255 (Wilson, J., dissenting) (âPerhaps the Majorityâs holding only stands for the proposition that irrelevant speech can be purged from a profession under the guise of regulating conduct.â). Even if one accepts that the courtâs holding is indeed so limited,46×46. The dissent argued that this limiting principle was both legally and practically irrelevant to the opinion: on its face, the courtâs rule extended to all speech in the examination room, id. at 1237 (Wilson, J., dissenting), and the majorityâs deference to the governmentâs conception of relevance would permit the state to define any speech it wished to ban as medically âirrelevant,â id. at 1255. Indeed, doctors did not accept that their inquiries, even when asked as a matter of course, were irrelevant, see id.; they were arguably not claiming the personal right to speak freely on irrelevant topics so much as the right to communicate truthful, relevant speech without undue state intervention. See id. at 1244 (â[T]he Act . . . prohibits licensed medical professionals from . . . making inquiries . . . that they believe will improve the well-being of their patients.â); cf. Robert Post, A Doctor Has Limited First Amendment Rights, N.Y. Times: Room for Debate (Aug. 21, 2014, 2:03 PM), http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2014/08/20/when-do-doctors-have-the-right-to-speak/a-doctor-has-limited-first-amendment-rights [http://perma.cc/9LKZ-CH6S] (suggesting that âpoliticizedâ laws that âprevent[] doctors from communicating relevant knowledgeâ to their patients âfrustrate[] an underlying purpose of the First Amendmentâ). These criticisms are important, and they illuminate many of the problems with the courtâs rule, yet so too do they elide the problem this comment seeks to explicate: it is in accepting the courtâs limiting principle â not rejecting it as illusory â that the unprecedented breadth of Wollschlaeger and its effects on expression become clear. analysis of this supposedly limiting principle reveals not the reasonableness of the courtâs rule, but its unprecedented breadth and problematic normative implications.
To understand the breadth of the courtâs withdrawal of protection, it is first necessary to understand what the court, and Florida, mean by âirrelevant.â Seeking to define the medical relevance requirement for purposes of the petitionersâ vagueness challenge, the court explained that â[i]f . . . the physician seeks firearm information to suit an agenda unrelated to medical care or safety, he or she would not be making a âgood faithâ inquiry.â47×47. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1228 (emphasis added). There is little mystery as to what âagendaâ means: it is the courtâs, and the legislatureâs, pejorative term for a doctorâs desire to communicate a political opinion to her patients.48×48. The dissent is explicit on this point: the âagendaâ the legislature sought to curb constituted âirritating politicking on the subject of firearm ownership.â Id. at 1248 (Wilson, J., dissenting); see also id. at 1231 (writing that the Act âproscribe[s] . . . political discussions between private citizensâ). Indeed, the majority not only referred to the banned speech as animated by a political agenda, but also went so far as to acknowledge that speech on firearms may indeed be speech on a âmatter of public concern.â49×49. Id. at 1221 (majority opinion). To the court, then, âirrelevant speechâ is not simply irrelevant: it is political speech or speech on a matter of public concern â speech that Pickup excluded from its sphere of First Amendment exemption, and crucially, speech that precedent holds receives the highest degree of protection under the First Amendment.50×50. See Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207, 1215 (2011) (â[S]peech on public issues occupies the highest rung of the hierarchy of First Amendment values, and is entitled to special protection.â (quoting Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138, 145 (1983) (internal quotation marks omitted)) (internal quotation marks omitted)); Citizens United v. FEC, 130 S. Ct. 876, 898 (2010) (â[P]olitical speech must prevail against laws that would suppress it, whether by design or inadvertence.â).
Analyzing the Wollschlaeger courtâs supposedly limiting principle, then, reveals the opinionâs problematic breadth: Wollschlaeger removes all protection from even the most protected form of communicative speech51×51. This speech is protected for a reason. See Snyder, 131 S. Ct. at 1207 (âThe First Amendment reflects âa profound national commitment to the principle that debate on public issues should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open.ââ (quoting N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 270 (1964))); Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 898 (finding such debate âa precondition to enlightened self-government and a necessary means to protect itâ); cf. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1231 (Wilson, J., dissenting) (noting that patients will ânow . . . know lessâ about firearm safety). simply on the basis of where and by whom it is uttered. More troublingly for purposes of precedent, the court, in emphasizing the banâs limitation to irrelevant speech, seems to have removed protection in part because, not in spite of the fact that the speech is communicative expression on a matter of public concern. Thus, whereas Pickup exempted speech because it had the characteristics of therapy,52×52. See Pickup v. Brown, 740 F.3d 1208, 1231 (9th Cir. 2014) (â[T]alk therapy . . . stands on the same First Amendment footing as other forms of medical or mental health treatment.â). Wollschlaeger exempted speech from any First Amendment protection in part because it had the expressive characteristics of speech.53×53. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1221 (â[T]he privacy of a physicianâs examination room is not an appropriate forum for unrestricted debate . . . .â). To be fair, the majority suggested Pickupâs line between treatment and speech is an amorphous, and thus expansive one, ostensibly mitigating the critical weight of this comparison. See id. at 1224 (suggesting an inquiry about gun ownership could be the âopening salvoâ in a course of treatment). Yet though this criticism of Pickup may be apt in theory, the majorityâs use of it in Wollschlaeger to vastly expand Pickupâs zone of unprotected speech was highly problematic. See id. at 1248 n.16 (Wilson, J., dissenting). First, Pickup hardly went out of its way to carve out a category of protected speech related to treatment only to have it erased: to explode this dichotomy is to abandon the limiting principle that, to the Pickup court, likely made its approach reasonable in the first place. And second, however broadly one construes Pickupâs rule, speech âirrelevant to medical careâ cannot plausibly be categorized as treatment.
More problematic than the breadth of the courtâs rule is the normative premise its so-called limiting principle reveals: that it is mere âcommon senseâ that a doctor, as a professional, has no right to express to a patient her religious, political, or moral beliefs â all irrelevant to medical care â no matter how central those beliefs may be to her citizenship. On the one hand, this premise is flawed in and of itself: it reflects a highly regimented54×54. Cf. Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 514 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting) (âOf course a physician can talk freely and fully with his patient without threat of retaliation by the State. The contrary thought . . . has the cast of regimentation about it, a cast at war with the philosophy and presuppositions of this free society.â). vision of American professionalism that the High Court has increasingly disclaimed, that a personâs expressive life may be â even must be â firmly separated from her professional one.55×55. The Court has held, albeit for purposes of interpreting the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, that the fact that a corporation seeks profit does not mean it cannot engage in religious exercise, and that for the State to impose that rigid subdivision on citizens by conditioning the benefits of incorporation on the renunciation of expressive rights is problematic, see Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 134 S. Ct. 2751, 2767 (2014) (â[The state] would put . . . merchants to a difficult choice: either give up the right to seek judicial protection of their religious liberty or forgo the benefits . . . of operating as corporations.â); id. at 2771, just as the Court has refused to remove First Amendment protection from commercial communication in part because of a rejection of the argument that such speech is categorically distinct from noncommercial expression, see Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 131 S. Ct. 2653, 2671 (2011) (âThe commercial marketplace, like other spheres of our social and cultural life, provides a forum where ideas and information flourish.â (quoting Edenfield v. Fane, 507 U.S. 761, 767 (1993)) (internal quotation mark omitted)). Regardless of oneâs opinion of the merits of these cases, cf. Hobby Lobby, 134 S. Ct. at 2787 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (speaking of the effect of the majorityâs accommodation on âthird partiesâ), and conceding that they addressed distinct legal questions from that in Wollschlaeger, they nevertheless reflect an aspirational vision of American citizenship in which a citizen need not, and the state may not, draw impermeable lines between professional, commercial, and expressive existence, dividing citizenship into non-overlapping zones and, on the basis of this regimentation, withdrawing all protection for expression the moment a citizen travels from one zone to the other. On the other hand, even those who would agree with this bifurcated vision of professional and expressive speech â who would choose it as their own standard â should balk at the courtâs decision, in eliminating protection from such speech, to impose this vision on all doctors. Doctors surely have some right to define and delineate the boundaries of their own professional and expressive lives.56×56. Cf. Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992) (âThese matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, . . . are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.â). As all people do throughout their careers, a doctor must decide how important it is for her to communicate her personal beliefs to clients, what she is willing to risk in order to do so, and whether she is willing to pay the market price for her choice.57×57. Cf. Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1230 (Wilson, J., dissenting) (âIndeed, some doctors believed these conversations [about gun safety] to be so important that they were willing to lose the business of patients who refused to engage.â). This right of expressive self-definition is not absolute,58×58. This comment does not suggest that the recognition of a doctorâs speech rights should in all cases prevent a state from restricting them. A state may have legitimate purposes sufficient to justify a restriction, pursuant to some form of First Amendment scrutiny. See Laurence H. Tribe, The First Amendment Should Protect Disfavored Viewpoints, N.Y. Times: Room for Debate (Aug. 20, 2014), http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2014/08/20/when-do-doctors-have-the-right-to-speak/the-first-amendment-should-protect-disfavored-viewpoints [http://perma.cc/N83V-ZNBG] (acknowledging statesâ interests in âprotect[ing] patient safety and privacy,â but rejecting the absence of scrutiny in Pickup and Wollschlaeger). The courtâs error was not in recognizing these interests but in applying no scrutiny and thus clearing the way for the state to use these interests as smokescreens through which to effect âpolitically motivated discrimination against disfavored viewpoints.â Id.; see also Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d at 1238 (Wilson, J., dissenting). yet it demands some recognition. In failing to accord any value to a doctorâs nonmedical expression to a client, the Wollschlaeger court effected a broad transformation of a doctorâs rights as a citizen through a simple, unexamined admonishment: it is not a doctorâs job to talk to her patients about politics.
Perhaps to many this criticism sounds idealistic: conceptions of citizenship notwithstanding, the intimacy of a doctorâs office is no place for political speech.59×59. Cf. William M. Sage, Unpacking the Regulation of âProfessional Speech,â Balkinization (Oct. 13, 2014, 10:30 AM), http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/10/unpacking-regulation-of-professional.html [http://perma.cc/AR3A-NSWX] (âThe fiduciary bond between a professional and a client often depends on verbal interaction to build intimacy and trust . . . .â). Indeed, even some scholars who would likely reject the withdrawal of scrutiny in Wollschlaeger might nevertheless accept the normative premise therein. See, e.g., Post, supra note 46 (rejecting a doctorâs âpersonal First Amendment rights to speak as she wishesâ but suggesting she may act as a âconstitutional spokeswomanâ for her patientsâ âright[] . . . to be informedâ). Yet it is vital to recognize that in exempting this speech from scrutiny, the Wollschlaeger court did more than just deny the expressive rights of doctors: it handed the state â the very entity the First Amendment cautions the court to distrust60×60. See Citizens United v. FEC, 130 S. Ct. 876, 898 (2010) (stating that the First Amendment is â[p]remised on mistrust of governmental powerâ). â the power to censor a doctorâs expression with almost complete judicial deference. Even those who would agree with the courtâs premise, then, should recognize the independent normative dangers of its rule61×61. See Keighley, supra note 39 (noting that Wollschlaegerâs breadth gives states the power to âregulate medicine based on ideological motivationsâ); accord Tribe, supra note 58. : Wollschlaeger handed the state a ânew and powerful tool to silence expressionâ62×62. Pickup v. Brown, 740 F.3d 1208, 1216 (9th Cir. 2014) (OâScannlain, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). â one far more powerful than that constructed in Pickup itself.
There is no question that the Wollschlaeger court faced a difficult question: with what doctrinal frame should courts balance a doctorâs expressive rights against the regulatory interests of the state? The answer to this question is not obvious: though Pickup, Wollschlaeger, and King offer valuable insights,63×63. Pickup and Wollschlaeger each relied, in part, on the so-called distinction between professional, or occupational, conduct and speech â with each constructing different theories as to how speech might travel from one category to the other: in Pickup, on the basis of its status as treatment, in Wollschlaeger, on the basis of its utterance in the examination room. In King, the Third Circuit rejected this dichotomy between professional conduct and speech as largely âillusory,â King v. Governor of N.J., No. 13-4429, 2014 WL 4455009, at *7 (3d Cir. Sept. 11, 2014), agreeing with the Pickup dissentâs critique; it then applied intermediate scrutiny to a regulation of professional speech within the examination room, see id. at *15 (âIntermediate scrutiny is necessary to ensure that State legislatures are regulating professional speech to prohibit the provision of harmful or ineffective professional services, not to inhibit politically-disfavored messages.â). King thus aptly rejected the Pickup and Wollschlaeger rules as either inadministrable or normatively problematic. Whether or not intermediate scrutiny will prove to be the ideal frame, King is certainly the most speech-protective and effectively balanced decision thus far. the ultimate determination is beyond the scope of this comment. Nevertheless, it is imperative that future courts recognize not just the precedential flaws but also the normative dangers lurking in Wollschlaegerâs answer. The blurred lines between citizenship and professionalism in American society are not inconveniences to be erased by the state64×64. Cf. McCullen v. Coakley, 134 S. Ct. 2518, 2540 (2014) (â[T]he prime objective of the First Amendment is not efficiency.â); Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 869 (1992) (opinion of OâConnor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.) (âLiberty must not be extinguished for want of a line that is clear.â). : they are a vital element of American citizenship â and not only for doctors. There is a reason that the American Bar Association has petitioned the Eleventh Circuit for en banc review of Wollschlaeger.65×65. See Brief of the American Bar Association as Amicus Curiae in Support of Petition for Rehearing En Banc of Plaintiffs-Appellees, Wollschlaeger, 760 F.3d 1195 (No. 12-14009). The courtâs normative understanding of professionalism could as easily extend to a variety of professions â including law â and, indeed, a limitation of the courtâs rule to doctors presents its own doctrinal problems. See Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 899 (âSpeech restrictions based on the identity of the speaker are all too often simply a means to control content.â). When it comes to professional regulation, doctors are not the end but the beginning, the canary in the coal mine for the rest of us.